Rough draft of the intro for the Hitler and Rhetoric book

[Much of this is elsewhere on this blog. I’m curious if I’m still having the problem of being too heady and academic.]

Martin Niemoller was a Lutheran pastor who spent 1938-1945 in concentration camps as the personal prisoner of Adolf Hitler. Yet, Neimoller had once been a vocal supporter of Hitler, who believed that Hitler would best enact the conservative nationalist politics that he and Niemoller shared. Niemoller was a little worried about whether Hitler would support the churches as much as Niemoller wanted (under the Democratic Socialists, the power of the Lutheran and Catholic churches had been weakened, as the SD believed in a separation of church and state), but Neimoller thought he could outwit Hitler, get the conservative social agenda he wanted, disempower the socialists, and all without harm coming to the church. He was wrong.

After the war, Niemoller famously said about his experience:

First they came for the Socialists, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Socialist.

Then they came for the Trade Unionists, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Trade Unionist.

Then they came for the Jews, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Jew.

Then they came for me—and there was no one left to speak for me.[1]

Niemoller was persuaded that Hitler would be a good leader, or, at least, better than the Socialists. After the war, Niemoller was persuaded that his support for Hitler had been a mistake. What persuaded him either time?

Christopher Browning studied the Reserve Police Battalion 101 and its role in Nazi genocide, narrating how a group of ordinary men could move from being appalled at the killing of unarmed noncombatants to doing so effectively, calculatedly, and enthusiastically. German generals held captive by the British were wiretapped, and often talked about how and why they supported Hitler, many of whom had been opposed to him. In 1950, Milton Mayer went to visit the small German town from which his family had emigrated and talked to the people living there, writing a book about his conversations with ten of them, all of whom to some degree justified not only their actions during the Nazi regime, but the regime itself—even those who had at points or in ways resisted it. Melita Maschmann’s autobiographical Account Rendered, published in 1963, describes how she reconciled her Hitler Youth activities, which included confiscating property and helping to send people to camps, with her sense that National Socialism was idealistic and good. Robert Citino’s The Wehrmacht Retreats, David Stone’s Shattered Genius, and Ian Kershaw’s The End all describe how so many members of the German military elite not only reconciled themselves to working for Hitler, but to following orders that they believed (often correctly) meant disaster and defeat. Benny Morris’ Roots of Appeasement gives a depressing number of examples of major figures and media outlets that persuaded others and were persuaded themselves that Hitler was a rational, reasonable, peace-loving political figure whose intermittent eliminationist and expansionist rhetoric could be dismissed. Andrew Nagorski’s Hitlerland similarly describes American figures who were persuaded that Hitler wouldn’t start another war; accounts of the 1936 Olymplic Games, hosted by the Nazis, emphasize that Nazi efforts were successful, and most visitors went away believing that accounts of anti-Jewish violence and discrimination were overstated. Biographers of Hitler all have discussions of his great rhetorical successes at various moments, enthusiastic crowds, listeners converted to followers, and individuals who walked out of meetings with him completely won over. Soldiers freezing to death in a Russian winter wrote home about how they still had faith in Hitler’s ability to save them; pastors and priests who believed that they were fighting to prevent the extermination of Christianity from Germany still preached faith in Hitler, blaming his bad advisors; ordinary Germans facing the corruption and sadism of the Nazi government and the life-threatening consequences of Hitler’s policies similarly protection their commitment to Hitler and bemoaned the “little Hitlers” below him who were, they said, the source of the problems. The atrocities of Nazism required active participation, support, and at least acquiescence on the part of the majority of Germans—the people shooting, arresting, boycotting, humiliating, and betraying victims of Nazism were not some tiny portion of the population, and those actions required that large numbers walk by. Some people were persuaded to do those things, and some people were persuaded to walk past.

After the war, what stunned the world was that Germans had been persuaded to acts of irrationality and cruelty previously unimaginable. Understanding what happened in Germany requires understanding persuasion. And understanding persuasion means not thinking of it as a speaker who casts a spell over an audience and immediately persuades them to be entirely different. Rhetoric, which Aristotle defined as the art of finding the available means of persuasion, isn’t just about what a rhetor (a speaker or author) consciously decides to do to manipulate a passive audience. What the case of Hitler shows very clearly is that we are persuaded by many things, not all of them words spoken by a person consciously trying to change our beliefs. Rhetoric helps us understand our own experience, and the most powerful kind of persuasion is self-persuasion. What a rhetor like Hitler does is give us what scholars of rhetoric call “topoi” (essentially talking points) and strategies such that we feel comfortable and perhaps deeply convinced that a course of action is or was the right one. Rhetoric is about justification as much as motivation. That isn’t how people normally think about persuasion and rhetoric, and, paradoxically, that’s why we don’t see when we’ve been persuaded of a bad argument—because we’re wrong about how persuasion works.

This book is about Hitler, and yet not about Hitler. It’s really about persuasion, and why we shouldn’t imagine persuasion as a magically-gifted speaker who seduces people into new beliefs and actions they will regret in the morning. It’s never just one speaker, it’s never just speech, it’s never even just discourse, the beliefs and actions aren’t necessarily very new, and people don’t always really regret them in the morning.

[1] There are various versions. This one is from here: https://www.ushmm.org/wlc/en/article.php?ModuleId=10007392

What it’s like when you’ve been reading Nuremburg Interrogations, Tapping Hitler’s Generals, Shattered Genius, The End, The Wehrmacht Retreats, and Trump Administration officials saying they’re protecting America by standing by Trump

A recent anonymous editorial says, “We want the administration to succeed and think that many of its policies have already made America safer and more prosperous. But we believe our first duty is to this country, and the president continues to act in a manner that is detrimental to the health of our republic.”

This author, call them Franz, wants the Trump administration to succeed, and believes the administration is significantly damaging to the US. So, Franz wants an administration to succeed that he believes is damaging to the US. Wait, wait, that isn’t what Franz meant at all.

The problem with Trump is that he is basically a fascist. He doesn’t want a government accountable to the people through a critical press; he wants (and, to a large degree, has) a media that will repeat in a fawning way anything he wants said, that will defend him through any sophistries and casuistries and outright falsehoods necessary (how tall is he? how much does he weigh?).  Trump wants to be a one-person government, he wants to be head of a one-party state, in which there is nothing but fawning adoration of him, and a government of charismatic leadership. Franz thinks all of that is bad, and yet Franz does everything he can to keep Trump from being held accountable for how bad Franz thinks Trump is.

The sensible (and honorable) thing  for Franz to do would be to step outside the administration and call for impeachment. But Franz isn’t willing to do that honorable thing. Why not? Notice that Franz never explains that point. Franz wants to be seen as a hero without actually explaining why he hasn’t engaged in the genuinely brave action his beliefs would imply–openly condemning an administration he thinks is (sort of–he likes the political agenda, sometimes) bad, but not really, because not bad enough for him to take a hit to his political career.

Basically, this coward has done an anonymous negative Yelp review on Trump.

He says he likes the Republican, not Trump’s, policy agenda. Even without Trump, the GOP has Congress, a reliable propaganda machine, and an increasingly and openly Republican judiciary, and impeaching Trump would put Pence in power. So, why not do it?

Because, and this is what Franz doesn’t want to say, without rabid Trump supporters, the GOP wouldn’t have Congress. Franz wants the political energy and power gained by fomenting Trump’s fascism, but Franz thinks he doesn’t actually want fascism.

Oh, yes, he does. Franz doesn’t want the end product of fascism, but he wants the support of fascists. Franz supports fascism. Franz needs fascists. Maybe Franz should rethink his political agenda since 1) it depends on fascists, and 2) it depends on his hiding his ethical agenda from the public.

The German generals disliked Hitler from the beginning, recognizing him as pretty much a shallow thinker and an idiot about military affairs, and many of them were not Nazis, but they were reactionaries, and they loathed what they thought of as Bolshevism (which included liberalism and democratic socialism). They stuck with Hitler because they believed that “many of [his] policies have already made [Germany] safer and more prosperous.” They would have said that they supported his “effective deregulation, historic tax reform, a more robust military and more.” Because he did all that. Seriously, Hitler did that. Franz would have liked Hitler. Hitler undid the socialist agenda of the Weimar democracy in regard to regulations about labor, he promised industrialists all sorts of things, and he promised the military what it wanted.

Am I saying that Trump is Hitler? No, because I really don’t think he is, but I do think he’s a fascist (not in the loose way it’s thrown around in the media, but in the way scholars like Paxton describe it). I’m making a more complicated point: Franz is presenting himself as a hero and savior. Is he? And the way to answer that question is to ask whether we would praise the same behavior on the part of other people who made the same arguments Franz is. Franz’s way of defending Trump is how supporters of Hitler defended him. It’s a bad way of defending someone.

That was complicated, so I’ll try to be more clear. Franz says that he has to try to mitigate Trump’s awful behavior because he likes Trump’s policy agenda (and he thinks the two are separate). He can’t leave Trump because then he might not get that agenda. And that is exactly the way that various people justified working with Hitler.

Is Franz’s defense a good defense? No. Not because Trump is like Hitler, but because Franz is like the people who supported Hitler. Had Hitler had to rely only on true believers like Himmler and Goebbels, he would have tanked. He succeeded because of people like Franz.

It isn’t about the policy agenda. It’s about the world you create in the course of getting that agenda. That’s what supporters of Hitler didn’t understand, and it’s what Franz doesn’t understand. You’re supporting a toxic process because it will get you the momentary political gains. The momentary political gains don’t matter. The process does.

So, Franz, your desire to hold on to a GOP majority—that is, your tribalism—means you’re throwing the US under the bus. You’re trying to present yourself as a hero, but you’re an enabler. The kindest thing I could say about you is that you’re Franz. Were I less charitable, I’d point out that you’re Wilhelm.

The image is from here: http://ww2today.com/24th-september-1942-hitler-sacks-his-chief-of-staff-franz-halder

When Chester brought me a little dog

At one point in my life I was living in a wonderful house on an acre of land, and the front windows looked out to the mailbox. Chester Burnette (a Great Dane mix) was there, and so was Hoover (a Malamute). They had strong feelings about looking out that front window. We had put a couch against the front window, a big couch, but they moved it out of the way so many times we gave up and moved it against the other wall.

There was a woman in the neighborhood who had two tiny dogs, and she walked them with her sweatband and sock tassels matching. Every day, she walked them up to our mailbox, which our dogs could see, and let them shit there. And then she walked away. On weekends, Chester alerted me to this, and I knew he wanted me to do something about it, but, like unstable people who study psychology, I’m a scholar of rhetoric because I’m terrible at it. How do you say to someone, “Um, your dogs’ shitting here everyday is not chance. Dogs shit to send a message. You shouldn’t let them do that. And, by the way, pick that shit up.”? Well, you say it by saying it. But I was raised in a barn by wolves, and I’ll admit I was so gerfuddled by her matching tassel and headband and appalling bad manners that I just wasn’t dealing.

So, one day, when she brought her dogs to shit at our mailbox, Chester jumped a six-foot fence, and brought me one of her dogs.

He was saying, very clearly, deal with this.

At that point, things were complicated. She was freaking out, and I loaded her and her dogs into my car, and took them to the vet. And on the way she told me about how her marriage was disintegrating. It is a condition of my family that total strangers unload on us about their lives, and I’m usually okay with that. I like hearing about the lives of checkers, people on the bus, salespeople, but I was not prepared for this. Her husband, a dentist, was leaving her for one of his assistants, and I heard way more about their marriage and him than I ever want to know about anyone. Way, way more.

When we got to the vet, the vet pointed out that Chester hadn’t actually broken the skin of her dog, and I paid the bill, and I took her home, and heard a lot more about her very vexed relationship with an apparently awful person. As far as I could tell, though, she was fine with his being awful till he wanted to bang an assistant openly. Once his awfulness was open, she was claiming victimhood and shock and all sorts of things. But the story she had told me on the way to and from the vet was that he was an awful person she was enabling. She only cared now because his behavior might hurt her.

And I could only intermittently care about the fact that she was willing to enable awful behavior until it hurt her. I just cared that I had fucked up by not earlier objecting to her dogs shitting at my mailbox. And I’m convinced she learned nothing from that whole episode. She thought the problem was Chester fetching her dog, but it really wasn’t. Chester, and my mailbox, and even her dogs had nothing to do with her being in a really toxic relationship with her husband.

I sometimes wonder whether I should have tried to talk to her about her own enabling and toxic relationship with the awful dentist? I didn’t. I just paid the vet bill and drove her home.

She no longer brought her dogs to shit at our mailbox, so I guess there’s that. I guess Chester did the right thing. I’d like to think that she stopped wearing sweat bands and matching tassels to walk her dogs, but that’s probably hoping for too much.

Rhetoric and Hitler: an introduction

Martin Niemoller was a Lutheran pastor who spent 1938-1945 in concentration camps as the personal prisoner of Adolf Hitler. Yet, Neimoller had once been a vocal supporter of Hitler, who believed that Hitler would best enact the conservative nationalist politics that he and Niemoller shared. Niemoller was a little worried about whether Hitler would support the churches as much as Niemoller wanted–Hitler and the Nazis had exhibited a possibly purely instrumental support for Christianity. But,  under the Democratic Socialists, the power of the Lutheran and Catholic churches had been weakened, as the SD believed in a separation of church and state, and Neimoller thought he could outwit Hitler, get the conservative social agenda he wanted, disempower the socialists, and all without harm coming to the church. After the war, Niemoller famously said about his experience:

First they came for the Socialists, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Socialist.

Then they came for the Trade Unionists, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Trade Unionist.

Then they came for the Jews, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Jew.

Then they came for me—and there was no one left to speak for me.[1]

Niemoller was persuaded that Hitler would be a good leader, or, at least, better than the Socialists. After the war, Niemoller was persuaded that his support for Hitler had been a mistake. What persuaded him either time?

A colleague once said that, if Hitler hadn’t existed, rhetoric classes would have had to invent him. Hitler does seem an inevitable topos in arguments about politics. Godwin’s Law states that, as an internet argument goes on, the chances of Hitler being invoked rise, and someone saying “HITLER DID THAT TOO” is notoriously a sign that the disagreement has gotten caught in a nasty back eddy of anger and contempt. Argumentation theorists call it the fallacy of argumentum ad Hiterlerum, when someone tries to discredit a policy, argument, or opponent by accusing them of being just like Hitler.

This isn’t just an odd thing about the internet. The fact that comparing someone to Hitler is a sign of failed argumentation is a really sad thing about how Americans are arguing about politics, since that comparison should be something we make thoughtfully. If everyone is Hitler, then why make the comparison? It’s just a way of saying “I don’t like you.” If every law or order with which we disagree is just what Hitler would do, then we should either always and never be in a panic. Calling someone Hitler is what, in 1984 would be called “double plus ungood.” It is a very vague way to say, “Yuck.” And if every politician is Hitler, then no one really is, or it isn’t necessarily a bad thing, and that’s a weird conclusion—so it’s useful to try to figure out if a politician really is like Hitler.

If we agree that Hitler was disastrous for his country and our world, and I think we should, then we want to understand what happened, we need to understand what enabled him to rise to power, destroy democracy, start the most destructive war of history, drag a country into self-immolation, and deliberately plan serial genocides.

It’s important, therefore, to see if there really is another Hitler goosestepping toward us, and not just fling that accusation at any politician we dislike. If the “You’re just like Hitler” is something everyone throws around, then we can’t think effectively about whether this moment is concerning.

We can agree that various groups (internal and external to Germany) should have taken the threat of Hitler more seriously  long before they did, So, the first question of this course is: what would it mean for us to bring up Hitler in a way that usefully advances an argument rather than ends it? How should the example of Hitler function in our rhetoric?

1. Rhetoric

Aristotle defined rhetoric as “the art of finding the available means of persuasion in a given case.” Aristotle’s insight is that we rarely (or never) have available all the possible means of persuading others; we’re constrained by factors such as our audience’s existing beliefs, prior experiences, level of information, degree of conviction, how much credibility we have with that audience, and even such factors as time and technology (rhetorical constraints). For instance, if we have the attention of an audience for a very short amount of time, we have fewer options for persuasion than if we have their attention for a longer period.

Persuasion is a surprisingly complicated concept, much more than people realize. But, for now, let’s define it this way. Persuasion has three parts: the people we’re trying to persuade (our audience); beliefs we want people to have, to act as though they have, or to act upon (what we might call “claims”); second, the strategies available to get people to have those beliefs or behave in those ways.[2] And, as Aristotle pointed out, there are two general ways you can persuade: what is generally translated as “artistic” versus “inartistic” proofs. It’s an unfortunate translation, since what he means is that there are arguments within a rhetor’s control (the arguments s/he makes in speeches) and ones not open to the rhetor’s construction (not constructed by the rhetor, such as pre-existing beliefs, historical events, things other rhetors have said).

So, if we’re going to study Hitler’s rhetoric, we’re going to look at what beliefs/actions he wanted people to adopt, who those people were, and what strategies he used to get that adoption. And we’ll have to think about artistic and inartistic proofs, and what I’ll argue is that Hitler benefitted tremendously by inartistic proofs.

Relatively early, at least by the time of his autohagiography Mein Kampf, Hitler had certain goals from which he didn’t vary.[3] These were:

    • Aryans/Germans (he was, like most racialists, sloppy and muddled in his racial taxonomies) were entitled to political, economic, military, and cultural dominance of Europe;
    • Germany must become purely German (again, a muddled notion never clearly defined), and engage in a kind of intra-continental colonialism, taking over large parts of central and eastern Europe (the amount varied over time), making the current inhabitants essentially serfs of German settlers;
    • Germans were victimized by anything that didn’t allow them such dominance (such as other counties resisting the dominance);
    • Germany had been about to achieve such dominance in WWI, but was prevented from victory by a “stab in the back” on the part of Jews—who, he said, controlled the media, and caused Germans to give up;
    • The historical moment was a battle between fascism and Jewish-Bolshevism;
    • Germany could not achieve its divinely-determined end of a master race that dominated Europe as long as there were any Jews in Germany, so Germany (and all the lands it controlled) must become “free” of any Jews (or other genetically tainted groups);
    • democracy, with the attendant notions of human rights (including an apolitical judicial system, free speech, freedom of religion) and the benefits of public multi-party debate over policies, was a Jewish plot;
    • The New Germany would not have class conflict, although it would still have classes, because it would not have a rigid and snobbish hierarchy in which Aryans looked down on other Aryans—it would instead have a rigid and snobbish hierarchy grounded in race (this is what was meant by “national socialism”—equal opportunity for members of the same race, with all members of that race fully committed to the German nation);
    • He was destined by God to lead Germany to its victory over Jewish-Bolshevism and had been given almost supernaturally good judgment (on any topic), stamina, will, and luck;
    • Because his end goals were so good, any means that he used to achieve those ends were good. He was, therefore, entitled to lie, embezzle, order murders, attempt a coup, or anything else in order to get himself to a position where he could lead Germany to its destiny, and Germany was, therefore, entitled to exterminate any people, peoples, or nations that might inhibit (let alone stop) Germany’s attaining its goals. Hitler, the Nazis, and Germany were exceptions to the normal rules of ethics and behavior.[4]

Notice that Hitler didn’t have to persuade everyone to believe these claims; he needed to persuade a large number of people to allow him to act on them. And, as will be discussed later, lots of people (especially but not exclusively Germans) believed many or all of these things before Hitler rose to power—he rose to power because so many people believed enough of them. Many people believed in Hitler because they already believed in what he said; despite his reputation, he wasn’t such a rhetorically powerful individual that he, and he alone, magically converted Germans into mindless tools of his will.

In popular thought, Hitler is the gold standard for demagoguery, and it’s common to attribute to him—specifically to his extraordinary rhetorical power–Germany’s descent into serial genocides, a war of extermination, and irrational fanaticism. That isn’t how scholars of the Holocaust or World War II describe what happened, nor why it happened, however. In fact, they point out that Hitler’s popularity varied considerably from 1924-1945, and they argue that his popularity correlates more closely to political events than to his rhetoric.

In the early 20s, numerous people describe being powerfully moved by him, and the crowds getting unhinged with enthusiasm for him. In Munich, the biggest venues available to him weren’t big enough to hold all the people who wanted to see him. Then he tried to overthrow the government violently (despite having promised, on his word of honor, that he wuldn’t), and, when he came out from his very shortened sentence, the German economic situation was better, and he couldn’t fill the houses. His rhetoric was exactly the same as it had been when he was magical, but the magic wasn’t working. And that’s interesting. It means his popularity wasn’t purely a consequence of his rhetoric, but how his rhetoric fit with the historical and economic context.

When the world economy collapsed, the Nazis started doing better in terms of popularity, but they never had the votes for Hitler to take power as dictator (and, as the government was enacting more sensible economic policies, and the economy was improving, the draw of the Nazis was decreasing). For complicated reasons (explained later in the course), conservative political leaders who were completely unwilling to have a coalition government with the Democratic Socialists or Communists, decided that they could play Hitler—allow him in the government, and yet outwit him continually. He insisted on being brought in as Chancellor, and they agreed. After the Reichstag fire, Hitler insisted on dictatorial powers (something many of the conservatives had wanted anyway), but there weren’t enough votes to pass the necessary legislation. The government allowed the Nazis to arrest, threaten, and even kill communists and forbid any of them to vote in the Reichstag. In March of 1933, all the other political parties, except the Democratic Socialists (what we would call “liberals” or “progressives”)–including the Catholic party–voted for “The Enabling Act,” which gave dictatorial powers to Hitler.

They did this although Hitler had wobbly popular support in 1933. In the next two years (1933-34), his popularity increased, and it skyrocketed in 1939, as Hitler led his country into an unnecessary war. Between 1933 and 1939, it wobbled a few more times, but his rhetoric remained more or less consistent (1933 is an outlier); therefore, there isn’t some clean and clear line of causality between what he said in his speeches and articles and his popularity. He wasn’t some kind of all-powerful magical rhetor who waved a word-wand and transformed good people into bad. But his rhetoric mattered in some way; it mattered to the people who heard it at some times. So, the second question at the center of this book is what, if anything, did Hitler’s rhetoric actually do?

Further, scholars argue that the word magician narrative—that Hitler hypnotized the Germans—is not just false, but damagingly so. Immediately after the war, it was common to describe Hitler as a magician who transformed basically good Germans into monsters, and, so, now that he was dead, there was no reason to worry about “normal” Germans. Most of them, it was said, didn’t even know the gas chambers existed, and had nothing to do with it. The “evil genius of rhetoric” narrative, in other words, was useful for very deliberately not thinking about what “normal” Germans had to do with serial genocides, German exceptionalism, rabid militarism, and a war of extermination. But scholarship on the Holocaust made quite clear that genocide wasn’t limited to the gas chambers, that “normal” Germans had willingly supported and engaged in it.

There remains a scholarly debate about the extent to which Hitler changed the beliefs of Germans. Certainly, he and the Nazis changed many behaviors on the part of Germans, but was it primarily coercion? Did he change their fundamental values? Was it just a grinding down of normal behaviors so that people would, as in the case of the 101st Battalion, begin by being horrified by actions they would later find easy? If Germans’ beliefs were changed, it’s fair to say they were persuaded—but what persuaded them? A world of violence and coercion? Pervasive propaganda? Nazi successes? An improvement in the German economy? And which of those things should we call “rhetoric”? That’s the third question of this course—how do we describe the changes in belief?

Many observers reported feeling moved by Hitler’s rhetoric, and decided to join with him, some even choosing to die with him. If we decide that his rhetoric did help persuade people to support him, then we have the interesting question of whether he was “good” at rhetoric. That’s obviously a tremendous important question for thinking about how and what we teach in courses on writing, argumentation, persuasion, and communication. Was Hitler’s rhetoric unethical only because it was in service of unethical policies? If so, then teaching his methods to students would be morally neutral. This is sometimes called the “compliance-gaining” model of rhetoric—the goal of every interaction is to get the other person (or people) to comply with what you want; anything you do to gain that compliance is morally neutral. What makes your strategies good or bad is whether what you’re trying to get them to do is morally good or bad.

If, however (and I think this is the case), Hitler’s rhetorical strategies were essentially damaging to his community—if they ensured that people made decisions badly; if that kind of rhetoric is likely to end badly—then we should be teaching students to avoid and suspect any rhetoric that relies on those strategies. Rhetoric, in this view, isn’t a morally neutral set of moves, but itself has a moral valence.

Those, then, are the four questions this course will pursue:

    • if Germans were persuaded to do or believe things they wouldn’t previously have done or believed, what caused those changes?
    • what did Hitler’s rhetoric actually do?
    • is rhetoric morally neutral and ethical or unethical only on the basis of the rhetor’s goals? In rhetoric, do the ends justify the means?
    • finally when, rhetorically, is the comparison to Hitler a useful and productive move in an argument?

2. How does persuasion work?

To ask whether Hitler was persuasive, we have to decide what we think persuasion is and how it happens, and one of the reasons we end up in unproductive arguments about Hitler and rhetoric is that the dominant model of how persuasion works is not very useful.

The conventional model for persuasion is that a speaker or writer (rhetor)  has an audience who believes one thing, and the rhetor wants them to believe something else. You think that little dogs are not involved in the squirrel conspiracy, and I think they are, and so I will try to give a speech or write an argument (or make a movie or whatever—I will create a text) that will get you to comply to my point of view. I want you, by the end of my text, to have entirely rejected your beliefs about little dogs in favor of the one I have. If I present you with an effective text (speech, article, tweet, link), then, after hearing or reading my text, you will change to believing little dogs are part of the squirrel conspiracy.

By this model (which I think is silly), an effective text is one that causes that change of belief in the audience. This is called the “compliance-gaining” model (and there will be more about this later). If the audience’s belief does not change in the way the rhetor wanted, then, according to this model, she did not create an effective (i.e., persuasive) text. Every once in a while, someone does a study in which people who believe one thing are given evidence that their belief is wrong, and, sakes alive!, the people don’t immediately and completely change their minds! The study concludes (and clickbait articles announce) that this study proves that no one ever changes their mind, or that you shouldn’t even try to argue politics, or that no one changes their mind due to rational arguments (if the test text had statistics). But that isn’t what those sorts of studies show at all. What they show is that the compliance-gaining model is nonsense. Still, it’s the one most people have.[5]

Understanding what Hitler and the Nazis did means understanding that persuasion is very, very rarely a rhetor telling a hostile audience that they are wrong and giving them information that causes them to adopt new beliefs. The most effective persuasion makes you think you’ve always already believed this argument because it fits so sweetly with things you already believe (this is an instance of enthymematic reasoning). The most powerful rhetoric fits so neatly with your situation, and your need to manage cognitive dissonance, that it doesn’t look like rhetoric. The most powerful rhetoric, in that sense, is probably not the best rhetoric for a community, but that’s something discussed toward the end.

These studies show that giving people a single text with acontextual new data doesn’t change their minds on important issues: those studies don’t show that data is ineffective, nor that people never change their minds. What they show is that people are resistant to change our beliefs, and that’s probably true, and probably good. In its own way, it’s rational. We don’t change our minds about a belief we value on the basis of one counter-argument presented in a psych lab because we really shouldn’t under those circumstances. And that makes sense, since otherwise people would be flopping from one belief to another. We do change our minds, but how quickly and easily we do so depends on what the belief is, how important it is to us, what beliefs it’s connected to, who is trying to get us to change our minds, and what kinds of arguments they’re making.

The more that a belief is connected to our sense of identity, especially our sense that we are, on the whole, a good person (and that people like us are, at base, good people—that is, the more we are prone to the cognitive bias of in-group favoritism), the more resistant we will be to give it up, or to admit it is untrue (or even true but harmful). For instance, people for whom religion is important do change religions, but the change is rarely “monocausal” (that is, with only one cause). There might be a single text or experience that is the catalyst for the biggest moment of change (Augustine hearing the child say, “Pick up and read,” for instance), but that moment of change is dependent on lots of other moments, events, beliefs, experiences, texts. People change their political parties, careers, friends, lovers—we do change our actions, behaviors, and beliefs.

But, before I can explain that, there has to be a digression as to what we mean by “beliefs” comes up, and it’s a surprisingly complicated question. We have a lot of beliefs, and many of them conflict with one another, and we’re not even aware of all of them. For instance, I’ve noticed that some people refer to any cat they don’t know as a “she,” and any dog they don’t know as “he.” That behavior indicates an implicit belief that cats are more likely to be female and dogs more likely to be male (or that cats are somehow feminine and dogs masculine), but if I ask them if they think cats are likely to female, they’ll say, “Of course not.” That isn’t an explicit belief of theirs. Their explicit belief is that dogs and cats have comparable distributions of male/female, and it’s in conflict with the belief implied by how they refer to dogs and cats. I might believe superstitions are silly, and yet go to some trouble to avoid walking under ladders—my implicit and explicit beliefs don’t match.

This distinction between explicit and implicit beliefs is important, in that people have a tendency to assume that the motives and beliefs of others are transparent to us (this is a famous cognitive bias, and called “the fundamental attribution bias”), and that we can see into the souls of others. We’re also likely to assume that statements of belief are accurate—if someone says, “I believe that squirrels are evil,” we will think that’s what they believe (this is the process that Hitler used to gain legitimacy and normalcy). Hitler had, for years, expressed exterminationist, expansionist, and authoritarian beliefs, and had acted as though he sincerely believed those things, but, when he suddenly claimed to have entirely different beliefs, he persuaded people that his previous rhetoric was insincere and his current rhetoric was sincere. German voters faced the contradiction of a rhetor who had clearly said he did and didn’t believe that expelling Jews from Germany was necessary, that Germany should go to war as soon as possible, and that the war would be with the countries to the East. His rhetoric persuaded people to ignore his rhetoric. That’s an interesting contradiction (more on that later).

There are lots of contradictions in our beliefs.

Milton Mayer went to Germany after the war and spent a lot of time talking to ten different men who had supported Nazism. He mentions that one of them, the second time they talked, defended Nazi treatment of Jews saying “they ruined my ancestors for generations back. Stole everything from them, ruined them” (139). In a later conversation, Mayer says, this same person said, that up until the present, his family had never had any great troubles, never lost land or homes. So, he believed that every previous generation had been ruined and no previous generation had been ruined. Had Mayer pointed out the contradiction to his friend, it’s interesting to think what would have happened. That friend justified the Nazis’ treatment of the Jews, even after the war, on the grounds of antisemitic rhetoric. His beliefs were in contradiction.

What I want to argue is that one of the most powerful impacts that public rhetoric has is to enable people to manage those contradictions in our beliefs. After all, we often believe incompatible things, and there are moments that the contradiction is made present. That moment of contradiction is potentially a moment of growth, but it can also be a moment of retrenchment. Public rhetoric—the arguments and assertions we’re hearing around us—help us move toward growth or[6] insulation in the sense that you are shoring up other beliefs—protecting them from contradiction. Nazi rhetoric was so effective because it ensured that people only heard arguments and assertions that would facilitate insulation.

Melita Maschmann was a Hitler Youth who was active in kicking Poles off of their farms so that “good Aryan families” could take them over, and, at one point, this meant not just her personally throwing them out of their farms, but making sure those people took nothing of theirs that Nazis might value. She was robbing people. And her description of just how she managed to rob families without feeling sympathy is horrible and yet plausible. What she says about herself and the other young girls (your age or younger) who were kicking people out of their homes, stealing their belongings, and sending them to a vague fate was “There is no doubt that we all felt we stood there in the name of ‘Germany’s mission’ and that this mission afforded us safety to act and a mysterious protection” (149). She believed that the ends (“Germany’s mission”) legitimated the horror she was personally inflicting on people (the means). She was a Machiavellian.

She describes sometimes asking the SS officers where the Poles being thrown off of family farms, and they were given vague answers about their being moved to empty farms in the “General Government” area that didn’t entirely make sense, and she knew they didn’t make sense, even at the time. But, she says,

“These answers satisfied us. I have already told you how good we were at giving awkward questions a wide berth. Our subconscious generally took very good care to see that we never became involved in dangerous discussion at conscious level in the first place. Even if we had pressed on to the realization that there could not possibly be enough farms standing empty in the General Government for all those who had been expelled and that many of them would be abandoned to homelessness and the direst poverty, this discovery would still not have worried us. The Poles were our enemies. We must exploit the moment when we’re stronger than them, to weaken, their ‘national substance.’ Such arguments were called ‘political realism.’ I never admitted to the fact that we were basically planning to commit genocide.” (152)

Maschmann didn’t have the explicit belief that she helping exterminate these people, but she had beliefs that legitimated and caused exactly the actions that logically necessitated the exterminations of those peoples.

And Maschmann’s description is an epitome of what went wrong in Nazi Germany, and it echoes what Niemoller said. And there are four important points about how normal people came to engage in (or justify) appalling actions that thoroughly violated their supposed ethics:

    • they decided it was okay to violate their basic ethical system (“do unto others” “ the law should apply equally to all people regardless of the judge’s feelings” “don’t take pleasure in the pain of others”) because it was a situation of us v. them extermination—either the in-group would be exterminated, or we would exterminate all out-groups;
    • they were just trying to survive, stay out of the view of the Gestapo, be thankful for better basic conditions, and not do anything that would get them intro trouble;
    • that strategy of trying not to get in wrong with the Gestapo necessarily meant they would one day find ourselves being cruel to a Jew, leftist, Pole, or some other enemy of the Reich. At that moment, and we all have those moments, a person is faced with admitting that we are coerced into violating our ethics; we can choose punishment for doing the right thing; or we can do the wrong thing and try to persuade ourselves it was actually the right thing. And here rhetoric is crucial. Once we have been cruel, we have to find a way to resolve the cognitive dissonance of our sense of ourselves as good and kind people, and the bad and unkind thing we’ve done, and we have two choices: to admit that we are capable of behaving very badly, or rationalize our bad behavior. That rationalization enables other rationalizations. Choosing not to say hello to a Jew creates the cognitive dissonance of being a nice person and have done a shitty thing, and, unless we’re willing to admit it was a shitty thing (which might get us into trouble with the second point—with the Gestapo), we’re going to find a way to rationalize how badly we treated the Jew. So, our shitty treatment of that one Jew in that one circumstance might make us more likely to find antisemitic rhetoric persuasive.
    • The just world model (aka, just world hypothesis) says that people get what they deserve. Sadly, rather than being a model that makes us try to act in order to ensure that people get the good things they are currently denied (in- and out-group), this model encourages us to believe that people suffering have done something to bring it on. Maschmann describes the impoverished and hopeless state of the Poles whose property she is helping to steal and whom she is helping to displace as a reason they are less deserving of that property (ignoring that the Soviets had already passed through the area). She mentions that at the same time she thought ill-kept farms and homes were proof of the unfit nature of the Poles she didn’t draw the same conclusion about Germans with ill-kept homes and farms (she only realized that contradiction after the war).

We tend to justify our bad treatment of the out-group by attributing different motives to them, so that they deserve bad treatment—even if they are behaving in ways we rationalize on the part of the in-group (such as the ill-kept farms). We can explain behavior through internal (motives) or external (context) factors.

In-group Out-group
Good behavior Good motives Bad motives or external factors
Bad behavior External factors Bad motives

Thus, Germans (her in-group) shouldn’t be judged by their bad behavior (unkempt farms) but Poles (her out-group) shoud

In addition, the rhetoric about the “General Government”—even though it was implausible–enabled her to keep herself from thinking about the necessary consequences of her actions. To do her job, she couldn’t think about what she was doing; she just had to believe that she was right. She substituted belief for thinking. And she was able to do that because her model of how to reason was Machiavellian—the ends justify the means. So, Maschmann’s in the moment thoughts (what she thought—her cognitive processes) seemed to be justified to her because they fit within a way of thinking about how to think (her metacognition). If, instead of thinking “the ends justify the means,” she believed, “do unto others as you would have them do unto you,” she couldn’t have done what she did, or believed what she did.

Ethics isn’t about what you believe; it’s about how you believe. It’s about how you assess whether your way of thinking is a good way to think.

Macschmann describes moments of being aware that she was violating her ethics, that she was tamping down empathy, but she pulled on things she’d been told by propaganda (rhetoric) to enable her to feel better about the obvious ethical contradictions in her behavior. When we’re in the mode of insulation—of trying not to think about what we’re doing–, we persuade ourselves (generally with help from public rhetoric) that the contradiction is manageable, and doesn’t require we seriously reconsider our commitments or sources of information. Rhetoric often serves to make us feel comfortable with beliefs we already have.

Some social psychologists describe a pyramid of harm. Imagine that you do one pretty awful act to someone else, that violates your ethics. You now have a lot of cognitive dissonance between your sense of your self as a good person who does good things, and this shitty thing you have done.

To take a less fraught example, I might believe that Hubert is a completely evil political figure, and that all Hubertians are fools at best and corrupt at worst, and I am especially worked up about Hubert’s having been shown to be friendly to little dogs. For me, this is an irrefutable datapoint for why any sensible person would reject Hubert. It also makes me angry. Just thinking about the photos I’ve seen of him with little dogs makes my blood pressure jump; I believe that his cavorting with little dogs shows the complete moral bankruptcy of him and everyone who supports him. I believe there is no excuse for what Hubert has done because playing with little dogs is unforgiveably bad. Then imagine that I am shown a picture of my favorite candidate, Chester, cavorting with a little dog. I’m faced with conflicting beliefs:

    • I believe candidates who play with little dogs are evil;
    • I believe Hubert is evil;
    • I believe Hubert supporters are idiots for supporting someone who plays with little dogs;
    • I believe Chester is good;
    • I am looking at evidence that Chester played with little dogs.

These beliefs create cognitive dissonance, and I have various ways I can reconcile them. Basically, I can reject and/or modify any of those five. I might decide that I was entirely wrong to condemn Hubert for playing with little dogs, thereby also changing my opinion about Hubert supporters (this is the least likely, for reasons explained later). I might decide that Chester is not good; I might decide that the evidence is fake; I might decide that there are exceptions to playing with little dogs, and it really has to do with someone’s motives in playing with them; I might decide it wasn’t really playing.

Which of those I choose will depend on whether any of those beliefs is attached to my sense of identity (as a good person, a good or bad judge of political figures, committed to hating little dogs, being better than Hubertians), how often I’ve taken those stands in public, whether my commitment to one of those stands has caused harm (oddly enough, if I’ve caused harm to others through my commitment to a belief, I’m less likely to abandon it without a fight), and the relative ranking of their importance to me.

The more that I identify with Chester—that I believe he is the same sort of person I am, that he really understands me, that he represents me—the more committed I will be to protecting my beliefs about him from disproof. If my commitment to Chesterianism is what scholars of rhetoric call “identification through antithesis” (or “unification via a common enemy”) then my commitment to Chesterianism is dependent on our group (the in-group) being as good as the other group (Hubertians, the out-group) is bad. Chester and Hubert engaging in the same behavior is really threatening to my sense of my group being absolutely good. We get pleasure from feeling better than the out-group, and so, the more that my in-group identity (Chesterians) is dependent on our being better than the out-group (Hubertians)—the more I engage in zero-sum thinking about groups, the more I will feel personally attacked and very threatened by anyone who points out that Chester played with little dogs. Under those circumstances, I will declare that the photo is faked, the photo comes from a bad source (I’ll called them “biased”), the people who make this argument have bad motives, and so I don’t even have to engage with their argument that Chester played with little dogs (that’s called motivism).

If my sense of self-worth is entangled with my belief that Chester is good (charismatic leadership, explained later), then I will defend Chester just as much as I would defend myself. If my commitment to hating little dogs is just as strong as my sense that Chester’s success or failure are mine (that I identify with Chester), then this photo presents me with very loud and insistent cognitive dissonance.

If it’s important to me to believe that Chesterians are inherently better than Hubertians, and that Chester is good, and that I have good judgment about politicians, my most likely response is to make distinctions on the basis of motive. And there are two ways I will flick away the clear evidence of my beliefs being in conflict. First, I will make all sorts of distinctions—this might look like playing, but it’s really training, or chastisting, or self-defense (that move is dissociation). Or, I might attribute different motives to Hubert’s playing with dogs from Chester’s doing exactly the same thing. Hubert is playing with them because he’s evil, but Chester is “playing” with them in the sense of playing a fish. This move is a combination of the fundamental attribution error (that you believe you can see the motives of everyone else, so you know the motives of Chesterians v. Hubertians), in-group favoritism (you attribute good motives to your in-group, Chesterians, and bad motives to any out-group for exactly the same behavior) and motivism (you don’t need to listen to the arguments of people you have decided have bad motives).

If your sense of your self is strongly connected to Chester being always good, then you can use those moves to kick the disconfirming evidence to the curb.  If I don’t have that kind of commitment to Chesterianism, then I don’t feel personally attacked by someone showing the photo, and I can think reasonably about what the photo means. If my belief about little dogs is much stronger than my commitment to Chester, then I might find it easy to change my mind about supporting Chester.

The more that I identify with Chester—I think he gets me and I really know what he’s thinking—the less I am likely to try to argue his policy proposals through the stock policy issues (explained below). There is an interesting kind of circle here. A lot of people believe that the world is divided into binaries—you’re either good or bad, right or wrong, certain or clueless, with us or against us. Those people think in binary paired terms (what Perelman called philosophical paired terms). So, for people who think that way—in binary paired terms—the central pair is in-group v. out-group. Therefore, if you can find any way that a person presenting an argument that makes you uncomfortable is connected to one of the bad terms in your sets of binary paired terms, you can just not consider what they’re saying.

Binary paired terms is probably the concept in my classes with which students struggle most, and yet it’s the one a lot of students identify as the most useful. Basically, it’s how you get suckered.

If you value bunnies, and your culture persuades you that valuing bunnies is necessarily connected to being a true American, and you’re prone to thinking in binary paired terms, then you’re likely to conclude that someone who doesn’t value bunnies is a bad American.

Here’s how you reason. A person either values bunnies, or they don’t. A person is either a good American, or a bad American. It’s paired terms.Like a lot of logical fallacies, it’s preying on a way of reasoning that can be logical.

Imagine this way of reasoning:

Notice that mammals and mammary glands do have a necessary logical connection (that’s the definition of mammal). But “real Americans” and “liking bunnies” aren’t necessarily connected; it’s an arguable connection. So, If someone wanted to assume that liking bunnies and being American are necessarily connected, she’d need to be willing to argue the connection, with citations, reasons, and examples. When we’re reasoning from paired terms, however, we just get angry when someone contradicts our association.

If we aren’t willing to argue (and not just assert) the connection, then this isn’t logical reasoning at all, but reasoning by association. You assume that all Real Americans like bunnies, so, if someone says they don’t like bunnies, you accuse them of not being a real American.  Or, “us” is to “them” as “liking bunnies” is to “not liking bunnies.”[7]

All of this is implicit. We don’t always know when we’re reasoning from binary paired terms. For instance, I was recently arguing with someone (call her Jane) who wanted to claim that a President (let’s call him Joe) was doing really well in regard to another country, and I pointed out that the consensus among people observing the situation, from every political perspective, including conservative, was that Joe was not doing well. Jane admittedly could not come up with any source to support her position, so, she argued that every source of mine was wrong because it was not conservative because it did not support Joe. Jane’s set of binary paired terms was this:


So, what you have to notice is that Jane had protected her beliefs from any disconfirming evidence. Jane can’t be proven wrong because her beliefs derive from her commitment to Joe—she can dismiss anything (usually as “biased”) that might challenge her beliefs about Joe. What’s important about this is that, if Joe does have flaws, Jane can’t hear them, and, therefore, Jane can’t learn—she can’t learn about Joe, or about Joe’s policies, or even about her own way of reasoning. The more that Jane supports Joe in public, the harder it will be for Jane to admit the error in supporting Joe, and the more that Jane can find herself supporting positions she would previously have rejected.

Jane’s political agenda has ceased being a coherent political agenda (although she can always find assertions to support her Joe-generated political agenda), and it has become rabid factionalism.

As long as she is irrationally committed to getting information only from pro-Joe sources, Joe can get her to commit to policies she would have previously rejected, and keep her within his echo chamber because Jane has become convinced that political deliberation isn’t about listening to various points of view, checking data and sources, but is entirely about rabid factionalism. If Jane believes that good policies come from policies advocated by her in-group, then all she needs to know is that her in-group media says this is a good policy, and she will dutifully repeat the talking points her media has told her to say.

Here’s what Jane can’t do. (And here’s how to know if you’re Jane.) Jane can cite a lot of data (since her sources have told her talking points that include data), but she can’t cite sources. If really pushed, some Janes can get pressured into citing sources, but they can’t cite sources outside of their in-group. If you can’t cite sources, or you can’t cite sources outside of your in-group, then you are repeating propaganda.

Jane doesn’t hold the in- and out-group to the same standards. Jane can think she is, because she is well trained in whataboutism. Her media tell her what the out-group thinks, so she thinks she’s informed on both sides (inoculation), and she thinks she’s being fair because she’s pointing out that the “other side” is bad.

For Jane, then, issues about policies aren’t determined or debated on the basis of what the policies will or won’t do, but as though the important question (the only question) for every political issue is which group is better. First, you divide all political positions into in-group (narrowly defined) and out-group (everyone else). Second, you use any behavior on the part of any out-group member to smear all the various groups you’ve included in the out-group. Third, you refuse to listen to any descriptions of bad behavior on the part of in-group (since your pro-Joe media doesn’t mention them, unless it’s part of “Those people are nuts because they say this,” and they promptly give you a talking point for refusing to think about that criticism). So, once Jane has committed to Joe this way (it’s called charismatic leadership) she can think in zero-sum terms—as long as she can think of a way the out-group (aka, anyone who disagrees with her, or gives her information she doesn’t like) is bad, she can feel good about being better.

Pointing out that people are condemning behavior in the out-group that they defend in the in-group can be good, and useful, if it’s part of an argument that we should hold all groups to the same standards, and the failure to treat all parties the same can be a sign that someone’s position is irrational. But, if we’re going to make the “why are you condemning this behavior and not that” in good faith, then you’re inviting an argument about the relative importance of the various behaviors, actors, consequences. If it’s a move toward exploring those issues, it’s interesting.

Usually, however, it’s an attempt to clear the in-group of all bad behavior, so that one (perhaps apocryphal) instance of “bad” behavior on the part of the out-group clears the in-group of any accusations of that sort of behavior. So, for instance, pro-slavery rhetors would invoke that some abolitionists had appeared to advocate violence in order to wipe off the slate the persistent and omnipresent violence of slavery. In this class, you’ll see the Nazis engage in the same rhetoric—their extermination of Jews was justified as self-defense, they said, because some people they said were Jewish (they weren’t always) had killed a Nazi.

As you’ll also see, many Germans felt that their actions against Jews, Sintis, Romas, Poles, homosexuals, socialists, and so on were expiated because they had been bombed—in the course of the war they started. That’s whataboutism at its worst.

Whataboutism is a “get out of criticism free” card, that flattens the actions of various groups (any bad behavior on the part of the out-group neutralizes all bad behavior on the part of the in-group). It also shifts the stasis. In policy argumentation, the stasis should be about what policy is best for the community as a whole. Identity politics makes the stasis which group is better (and authoritarians are all about identity politics). Whataboutism is an attempt to shift the stasis from what the in-group accused has done to what some (any) member of the out-group has done. And, ultimately, it rarely matters.

If I say that Chester lied, then someone saying that Hubert lied doesn’t make what Chester said true. Chester is still a liar. Whataboutism is all about distracting Chesterians from that fact.

Jane won’t see it that way; Jane doesn’t think there is an issue with her refusing to look at anything that might disagree with her, because she believes that the only proof that she needs that her beliefs are true is that she has those beliefs. The more that Jane consumes pro-Joe media, the more that media says that her sense of herself as a good conservative is connected to Joe, the more that she is a naïve realist (that she believes that, if she believes something, it must be true, and that her belief that something is true is all the evidence that is needed)[8], the less able Jane is to argue her position rationally, and the more likely she is to dismiss disconfirming evidence on the grounds that it’s disconfirming.

Here’s how that argument works: instead of assessing the validity of an argument on the basis of how it’s argued (methods that apply across groups), an argument is assessed purely on the basis of whether it is loyal or disloyal to the in-group.

For instance, Ward Churchill characterized people killed in the World Trade Center as “little Eichmanns” and got a lot of grief about it. A self-described lefty relative of one of the people killed in that attack condemned Churchill, and I found myself in an argument with someone (call him Floyd) who insisted the relative, despite what he said, couldn’t really be lefty; he must be conservative. Here was Floyd’s argument:

Jane and Floyd’s arguments were equally irrational, in the sense that neither could

    • make an argument that applied principles of reasoning across in- and out-group
    • identify the conditions of falsification (what would make them admit they were wrong)
    • make an internally consistent argument for their position.

Instead, both were reasoning deductively (and in a circular way) from and about group loyalty. Both were using their thinking in ways that justified their sense of their in-group. And neither could admit significant criticism of their way of thinking, so that both could (and can) go through life cheerfully finding confirmations of their beliefs and yet never reconsidering their beliefs. They are both profoundly irrational people who think they have reasons.

When you think of political participation as nothing more than supporting—in any way you can—people who you think embody your values, then you’re a sucker.

So, let’s think about what it would mean to involve yourself in politics in a way that didn’t mean rabid identification with a political figure or party. Let’s go back to the example of Chester being photographed with little dogs. If I am not particularly identified with Chester—if, for instance, I’m more concerned about policies than in-group identification—then I probably never rely exclusive on in-group media for information, and I certainly wouldn’t in this instance.

But, the more that in-group loyalty is important to me, the more likely I am to rely exclusively on in-group media, and I’d turn to in-group media in order to understand how to resolve the cognitive dissonance. That’s what both Jane and Floyd did (and do). And the more they are likely to spend their lives entangled in the inability to argue reasonably for the policies they support.

One of the functions of much public rhetoric is to give members of our group (religion, political party, discipline, team) talking points that will enable them to reconcile cognitive dissonance created by our beliefs being in conflict. The most obvious strategy would be to deny the accuracy of the photo. Chester TV would have pundits claiming it’s faked, the source of the photo is untrustworthy, it’s all a Hubertian plot. This is a kind of persuasion, and much rhetoric, I’ll argue, functions in exactly this way: to reconcile cognitive dissonance in such a way that previous beliefs are protected, confirmed, and possibly strengthened. This is effective rhetoric, not in that it changed a fanatical Chesterian’s belief about Chester, Hubert, or Hubertians to opposite beliefs—it doesn’t give someone new beliefs, as much as renewed commitment to pre-existing ones. A fanatical Chesterian wouldn’t have changed their mind about Chester or little dogs, but would have found a persuasive way not to change their mind about either. That’s the goal of such rhetoric. It’s in-group confirmation.

Chester TV might also have pundits saying that it wasn’t really a little dog, but a puppy, or Chester did it just in a clever political ploy, or had different motives from Hubert so it wasn’t really a bad thing to do. Chester TV might make the argument that Chester’s playing with a little dog doesn’t mean the same thing it does for Hubert—for Hubert, it’s proof that he and his followers are evil, but for Chester, it doesn’t mean that.[9]

Notice that this rhetorical relationship doesn’t quite fit the compliance-gaining model mentioned above. There isn’t a rhetor trying to get someone else to change views; there is rhetoric offered to someone who might use it to make themselves feel better about a belief they already have (or do something they intended to do anyway). The most important kind of persuasion is self-persuasion.

We want to think of ourselves as good people, and so express views that are what a good person would say, but do we really believe them? For instance, in 1942, Earl Warren, then Attorney General of California, testified before a Congressional Committee that “the Japanese” (he actually used a racist term) couldn’t be near the coast, power plants, water supplies, factories, military installations, farms, or forests. That’s an argument for putting them in prison. But, when asked if he was advocating imprisoning them, he said he wasn’t advocating any particular policy. But he was—the entire logic of his argument made imprisonment the only possible solution. I’m sure he really believed when he said he didn’t have a specific policy in mind, but I also think it’s possible that he just didn’t want to acknowledge to himself what he did believe. He just didn’t let himself think about the logical consequences of what he was saying.

There is another famous case, from Nazi Germany. Adolf Eichmann was in charge of various aspects of the Holocaust, especially transportation. When he was brought to Israel to stand trial for his central role in the concentration camps, the police officer in charge of interrogating him asked him about his role in the murder of Jews. Eichmann insisted, that although he was making sure that Jews were put on trains that went to death camps where they would almost certainly be killed, he was not responsible for their deaths, since he didn’t actually kill them. He was engaging in an activity that would result in deaths, but he didn’t believe he was responsible because he was one step away from those deaths, and he could keep himself from thinking about them. He wasn’t antisemitic, he insisted, and didn’t intend to kill Jews, although he did intend and carefully plan, and ensure that Jews were sent to places where they would be killed.

There are two parts to this way of separating our beliefs about our actions from what a logical analysis of those actions would produce: 1) as in the case of Warren and Eichmann, don’t think about the inevitable and logical consequences of the action you are doing (or advocating); 2) since you didn’t think about those consequences, you can tell yourself you didn’t intend for those consequences to happen (you, therefore, don’t have bad motives). And rhetoric can help you feel better about your participation in such acts by enabling you to dissociate killing from real killing. Eichmann wasn’t helping to kill Jews; he was just helping to ship them. He could dissociate real from apparent killing.[10]

It’s interesting to note that Eichmann claims to have vomited when he saw a camp—the kind of place he was sending people–, Heinrich Himmler almost fainted when he saw the kind of deaths he was ordering, and Earl Warren recanted his stance on mass imprisonment of Japanese-Americans when he imagined children going to a camp. They could believe that what they were doing or advocating was okay until they were faced with clear images of the consequences—till they couldn’t not think about it.

Eichmann and Himmler went back to enabling the very thing that appalled them, of course, without seeing any problem. So, how should we characterize their “beliefs” about genocide?

Beliefs are stories we tell ourselves about us, our kind, our world, and others. It is possible to feel great conviction about any belief at a particular moment, and equally great conviction about a completely incompatible belief at the next moment. Sometimes that’s just effective lying (liars always persuade themselves first), and sometimes it’s just the sense that we don’t need to have principles that operate across beliefs. We don’t need to think about whether our beliefs are consistent with each other.

There are four ways of trying to figure out if one of your beliefs is true:

  1. Ask yourself if it fits with other beliefs that are important to you;
  2. Ask yourself if you can think of an example, an authority, or find any research to say it’s true (you might even google to see if you can find a supporting source);
  3. Ask yourself if it conflicts with other beliefs you have that are important to you;
  4. Ask yourself if you can find an example, an authority, or find any research to say it’s false (that is, try to articulate the conditions under which you would admit it’s a false belief).

Eichmann, Himmler, and Warren could all determine their beliefs were true by relying on the first two—they could find support for their notion that exterminating or imprisoning others on the basis of race fit with beliefs; they all had evidence that it conflicted with other beliefs. Warren, unlike Eichmann or Himmler, paid attention to the third. His horror at the thought of children being taken to camps was a belief that contradicted his belief that “the Japs” as he called them in his testimony, weren’t deserving of the same treatment he would want for him and people like him

Feelings are beliefs that need to be considered. Eichmann and Himmler considered their feelings about Jews, but not their feelings about camps. Warren did both. And so, although his role in the racist imprisonment of Japanese in the US is indefensible, he went on to be a powerful critic of race-based law. Neither Eichmann nor Himmler went on to any deeper understanding of anything. They went to deeper commitments to beliefs they found appalling if they really thought about them.

In other words, they were persuaded to act on some beliefs and not others because they were persuaded not to think about some things. So, one of the very important things that rhetoric can do is to persuade someone not to think, and that’s usually done through dissociation.

Sometimes rhetoric does get people to adopt new beliefs, and, when that happens, it’s typically done through enthymematic reasoning or repetition. Persuasion is limited by our previous beliefs—a rhetor can only move us so far.[11]

Enthymemes are compressed syllogisms, and there’s good research to suggest that we have a tendency to reason by syllogisms (although we probably shouldn’t). Humans tend to think in terms of categories, and to reason either inductively (from specific to general) or deductively (from general to specific). So, for instance, if the only three Canadians you have ever met love rap music, you’re likely to assume that Canadians like rap music (you’re likely to move from the specific cases of those three Canadians to a generalization about Canadians—that’s the inductive reasoning). Once you meet a fourth Canadian, you’re like to reason deductively, and assume she likes rap music.

The syllogistic form of that last argument would be: All Canadians like rap; she is Canadian; therefore, she likes rap.

But, we don’t generally put the first claim (the major premise) into our text—we just assume it (and we assume our audience agrees with it). So, if you and I were talking about having a free ticket to see a rap festival, you wouldn’t say to me, “Let’s invite Ella. All Canadians like rap; Ella is Canadian; therefore, she likes rap and would enjoy going with us.” That would be the syllogistic version. You’d use an enthymematic one. You’d say something like, “Let’s invite Ella; she’s Canadian.” You’d leave it to you to supply the missing connection—that all Canadians like rap. If I didn’t share that major premise—if I didn’t have the stereotype that Canadians like rap—I’d be confused. And, in fact, that’s what makes a lot of conversations confusing—that the people in the conversation don’t share the major premise(s).

In a good conversation, if I didn’t share your major premise, I’d say, “What does her being Canadian have to do with it?” and you’d explain. And then we might have a conversation about whether your major premise is right. In good conversations, people often end up having to talk about the not-shared major premises. In bad conversations, you’d just get mad at me for not understanding your argument. If I said, “I don’t think all Canadians like rap,” you’d need to be able to explain why or how you came to the conclusion you did. So, first, you’d to know not just what you think, but why you think it—what evidence you have for it. Second, you’d need to be able to step back from your belief about Canadians and think about whether it’s a reasonable way to think. If you said, “Well, every Canadian I’ve ever known loves rap,” I might say, “How many have you known?” And we might end up talking about whether generalizing from three people is a good way to draw a conclusion about a nation of millions. You’d need to be able to engage in metacognition.

A productive disagreement doesn’t just involve our giving one another reasons for what we believe, but being willing to think about whether the sorts of reasons we’re giving are good.[12]

If one of us is deeply committed to refusing to change our mind on the issue,[13] then we’ll keep the conversation from going to issues of the major premise or metacognition. If, for instance, you have told me that you think this little dog is good, and I’m a devoted Chesterian, then my most likely response is to attack you—“What are you, some kind of Hubertian?!” I might try to persuade you that your sense of your self as a good Chesterian would never like a little dog. My “What are you, some kind of Hubertian?” is a compressed set of claims:

    • only Hubertians say anything good about any little dogs;
    • being a Hubertian is bad.

That’s a pretty crummy argument, but it’s likely to persuade you that the dog isn’t cute (that is, to retract your claim) under various circumstances:

    • If, for instance, I’m a member of the Big Dog Police, and you have good reason to think you might end up beaten up or jailed for disagreeing with me;
    • if I’m your boss, and you have good reasons based on previous experience to think expressing affection for little dogs is likely to result in getting fired or being treated badly (even though I didn’t say that in this conversation);
    • if being seen as a good member of the Chesterians is economically, spiritually, or culturally important to you (such as your living in the Big Dog Co-op, and getting known as a Hubertian could get you thrown out of the community);[14]
    • any other circumstances in which disagreeing with me might have high costs;
    • if you believe the two claims above.

Notice the number of things that will influence even these factors—whether I’m slapping a nightstick in my hand as I ask you, whether I seem angry, amused, threatening, kidding; how well we know each other, what our previous experience with each other is.

And I don’t even necessarily need to get you to retract your claim mentally, if I can persuade you to shut up and never say anything  positive about little dogs again. We don’t often talk about that kind of persuasion but it’s important (and it’s especially important for understanding how rhetoric worked in Nazi Germany). I can persuade you to change your mind, or I can persuade you to change your behavior. In lots of circumstances, the latter is enough: if I persuade you never to defend little dogs, never say good things about them, never to identify or empathize with them, then I have gone a long way toward enabling a culture in which they are vilified, mistreated, expelled, or exterminated.

Persuading someone to be silent is a powerful kind of persuasion. And it’s one at which the Nazis excelled.

This is a slightly broader notion of rhetoric than many people have, since they think of rhetoric as only compliance-gaining policy advocacy. Aristotle said rhetoric is the study of the available means of persuasion, and, if I persuade you to stop defending little dogs by threatening you, then, by Aristotle’s argument, we need to include threatening as a kind of rhetoric (and I think we should). It’s ultimately a harmful one (but so is compliance-gaining), but it’s still one.

Another kind of rhetoric that people don’t always consider is sometimes called deliberation or, the term I prefer, good faith argumentation. In good faith argumentation, people are open to changing their minds, feel obligated to provide evidence and make internally consistent arguments, apply the rules the same across all interlocutors, avoid implicit or explicit threats, try to represent one another’s arguments fairly, strive to be accurate and honest (those aren’t always the same things), and otherwise follow the rules set out by the pragma-dialectical school.

  1. Parties must not prevent each other from advancing standpoints or casting doubt on standpoints.
  2. A party that advances a standpoint is obliged to defend it if the other party asks him to do so.
  3. A party’s attack on a standpoint must relate to the standpoint that has indeed been advanced by the other party.
  4. A party may defend his standpoint only by advancing argumentation relating to that standpoint.
  5. A party may not falsely present something as a premise that has been left unexpressed by the other party or deny a premise that he himself has left implicit.
  6. A party may not falsely present a premise as an accepted starting point nor deny a premise representing an accepted starting point.
  7. A party may not regard a standpoint as conclusively defended if the defense does not take place by means of an appropriate argumentation scheme that is correctly applied.
  8. In his argumentation, a party may only use arguments that are logically valid or capable of being validated by making explicit one or more unexpressed premises.
  9. A failed defense of a standpoint must result in the party that put forward the standpoint retracting it, and a conclusive defense of the standpoint must result in the other party retracting his doubt about the standpoint.
  10. A party must not use formulations that are insufficiently clear or confusingly ambiguous and he must interpret the other party’s formulations as carefully and accurately as possible.[15]

Following these rules is especially effective for policy argumentation. Policy argumentation involves someone make an affirmative argument for a plan and then people debating that case (or proposing another plan). An affirmative case requires:

    • a coherent narrative about there being a problem and what has caused it to happen (a narrative of causality) so policy argumentation requires that the rhetor(s) show
    • there is a significant problem (stock issue of significance)
    • and it will not go away on its own (inherency)
    • and it is a structural problem (so the solution must involve structural changes—structural inherency)
    • or, it’s an attitudinal problem (the people enacting policies have the wrong attitude—attitudinal inherency)
    • a description of the plan and arguments (not just assertions) that the plan
    • is feasible (it’s practical and possible within various constraints),
    • will actually solve the problem (solvency),[16]
    • will not have unintended consequences that make the plan cause more problems than it solves.

A negative case is one that disagrees at any or all of these points (these stock issues). It might dispute that there is a problem, or say that the affirmative case has the wrong narrative of causality (in which case the plan can’t work), or say the problem will go away if we give it time, argue the plan isn’t feasible, doesn’t solve the problem, or will have more costs than benefits.

One thing you should to which you should pay attention as you’re reading material for this class is whether rhetors are engaged in good faith argumentation and/or policy argumentation. What you’ll see is that they generally aren’t, and that’s interesting

3. Hitler’s rhetoric

As Nicholas O’Shaughnessy says, anyone looking at the devastation of World War II and the Holocaust is likely to wonder: “How was it possible for a nation as sophisticated as Germany to regress in the way that it did, for Hitler and the Nazis to enlist an entire people, willingly or otherwise, into a crusade of extermination that would kill anonymous millions?” (1) One answer, the one you’d probably get if you stopped someone on the street, is to attribute tremendous rhetorical power to Adolf Hitler. Kenneth Burke calls Hitler “a man who swung a great deal of people into his wake” (“Rhetoric” 191). William Shirer, who was an American correspondent in Germany in the 30s, describes that, listening to a speech he knew was nonsense, “was again fascinated by [Hitler’s] oratory, and how by his use of it he was able to impose his outlandish ideas on his audience” (131). Shirer says Hitler “appeared able to swing his German hearers into any mood he wished” (128). Shirer is clear that Hitler owed his power to his rhetoric: “his eloquence, his astonishing ability to move a German audience by speech, that more than anything else had swept him from oblivion to power as dictator and seemed likely to keep him there” (127). In this view, Hitler was (and is) the cause of the war and serial exterminations.

Scholars don’t necessarily agree, however. Ian Kershaw says, “Hitler alone, however important his role, is not enough to explain the extraordinary lurch of a society, relatively non-violent before 1914, into ever more radical brutality and such a frenzy of destruction” (Hitler, The Germans, and the Final Solution 347). While Hitler’s personal views were important, and neither the Holocaust nor war would have happened without his personal fanaticism and charisma, they weren’t all that was necessary:

Concentrating on Hitler’s personal worldview, no matter how fanatically he was inspired and motivated by it, cannot readily serve to explain why a society, which hardly shared the Arcanum of Hitler’s “philosophy,” gave him such growing support from 1929 on—in proportions that rose with astonishing rapidity. Nor can it explain why, from 1933 on, the non-Nationalist Socialist élites were prepared to play more and more into his hands in the process of “cumulative radicalization.” (Hitler, the Germans, and the Final Solution 57)

In other words, Hitler’s followers were not passive automatons controlled by Hitler’s rhetorical magic. So, how powerful was that rhetoric?

The answer to that question is more complicated than conventional wisdom suggests for several reasons. First, while Hitler was quick to use new technologies, including ones of travel, most of the Nazi rhetoric consumed by converts wasn’t by Hitler. People like Adolf Eichmann talk about being persuaded by other speakers, pamphlets, even books.

Second, no one claims that Hitler was a creative or inventive ideologue: “Hitler was not an originator but a serial plagiarist” (O’Shaughnessy 24). Joachim Fest said Hitler’s beliefs were the “sum of the clichés current in Vienna at the turn of the century” (qtd. in Gregor, 2), and Gregor says, “Neither can one claim that Hitler was an original thinker. There is little in his writings or speeches that we cannot find in the penny pamphlets of pre-1914 Vienna where he began to form his political views. His racial anti-Semitism rehearses the familiar slogans of many on the pre-war right. His visions of German expansion echo the ideas of the more extreme wing of the radical-nationalist Pan German movement [….] And, in essence, his anti-democratic, anti-Socialist sentiments similarly reproduce the conventional thinking of broad sectors of the German right from both before and after the First World War.” (2)

If Hitler wasn’t saying anything new, to what extent can we say he persuaded people? What did he persuade them of?

A closely related problem is that large numbers of Germans supported Hitler politically but rejected the central aspects of his ideology—such as his eliminationist racism and his desire for another war. Although he’d long been absolutely clear that those were central to his views, when he began to downplay them (especially in 1932 and 33), many people believed those were trivial aspects that could be ignored. Many people supported him strategically, especially the Catholic and Lutheran churches, both of which were outraged by the Social Democrats’ (democratic socialists) liberal social policies (e.g., legalizing homosexuality, supporting feminism, and, especially, breaking the religious monopoly on primary schools). Since Hitler and the Nazis were socially conservative, and Hitler promised to allow the churches more power than the Social Democrats would allow, many Protestants voted for Nazis, and the official Catholic Party (the Centre Party) Reichstag members voted unanimously for Hitler taking on dictatorial power (for more on this background, see Evans; Spicer).

Some scholars refer to “the propaganda of success,” by which they mean that Hitler gained the support of people not because he put forward good arguments, or even because of anything he said, but because they liked his locking up Marxists and Socialists, industrialists liked his support of big business, people liked the increased amount of order, they liked the improved economy, they liked his conservative social policies, a lot of Germans liked his persecution of immigrants, and a lot of people either liked or didn’t mind the legitimating and legalizing of discrimination against Jews (even the churches only objected to discrimination against converted Jews). And large numbers of Germans didn’t particularly like the idea of democracy—the premise of democracy is that political situations are complicated, and that there aren’t obvious solutions. Or, more accurately, there are solutions that appear to be obviously right from one perspective, but are obviously wrong from another perspective. Democratic processes assume that the various perspectives need to be taken into consideration, and so the best policy for the community as a whole will not be perfect for anyone and will take a lot of time to determine—many people would rather that a powerful leader make all the decisions and leave them out of it. After Hitler had been in power a year, many people felt that their lives were better, and that’s all they really cared about—that they were headed down a road that would make their lives much worse didn’t concern them because they didn’t think about it.

Finally, many people came to support Nazis because they liked that Hitler made them feel proud of being German again. He didn’t make them feel proud of being German by changing their minds about anything, but by insisting publicly and endlessly that they were victims—that nothing about their situation was the consequence of bad decisions they had made. He wasn’t saying anything that was new, but it was new for a political leader—he was simply the first major German political figure in a long time to say, unequivocally, Germany was for Germans, and Germans were entitled to run Europe (if not the world).

All these characteristics of Hitler’s relationship with his supporters—his lack of originality, strategic acquiescence, hostility to democracy, narrow self-interest on the part of many Germans, and the propaganda of success—mean that it’s actually an open question as to whether Hitler’s rhetoric was unique, let alone how much power we should ascribe to it.

Hitler did persuade people—people did act in ways that they wouldn’t have acted had it not been for him—but he didn’t do so through a single speech, nor on his own, nor even just through discourse. Hitler had a lot of “available means of persuasion” (to go back to Aristotle’s definition of rhetoric) and he used them. As mentioned before, Hitler didn’t necessarily have to get everyone (or even most people) to believe Nazi ideology; he had to get people to comply with Nazi policies, or at least not resist them. If they did believe the ideology, their compliance with the policies was likely to be more thorough, predictable, and less expensive, but belief wasn’t necessary. Someone who sincerely believed that all Jews were communist terrorists working to undermine Germany could be counted on to inform on neighbors, and might help round some up, but someone who sincerely believed that intervention was certain death could be counted on to stand idly by, and that was good enough.

For instance, Hitler persuaded the Germany military forces to support him, to fight to the very last, following orders that many of them believed were unwise. And he did so with various means. Robert Citino explains the German officer corps’ willingness to “be with him every step of the way:”

Although they were not all Nazis, and Hitler had not captivated them all in a personal sense, his sensibilities and his policies—antisocialism, anti-Bolshevism, and anti-Semitism—had produced at least a “partial identificiation” (Teilidentität) with his regime. His early successes had impressed them all: rearmament and restoration of German sovereignty; a series of bloodless border conquests, and then a refight of World War I against Britain and France. Next came an existential struggle against the Soviet Union in which the Wehrmacht obliterated all the customary, legal, ethical, and moral boundaries of modern war. Enough of them supported Hitler’s crusade against Bolshevism to suppress whatever scruples they might have felt about his call for an ‘annihilation struggle’ (Vernichtungskampf) in the east. Finally, there was a global struggle against every great power that Hitler could find, and he found a lot of them. Gradually, as things went bad, some began to mutter, and a small number of them decided to kill him. (281).

Notice that Citino is emphasizing that the members of the officer corps were persuaded to support Hitler and enact his decisions without necessarily believing his decisions were right, his strategy was correct, or even he was a good person. Some had blind faith in Hitler, some believed they were already in too deep, some believed it would be an impossible dishonor to violate the oath they had taken, some believed they had no choice. Hitler just had to persuade the members of the officer corps to follow his orders; he didn’t have to persuade them the orders were good.

It’s important to remember that one of the available means of persuasion is a credible threat of violence. For a threat to get compliance, the audience has to believe it’s credible, so there is an aspect of belief involved—but that belief can be as much a consequence of action as discourse. Threats of violence against dissenters and critics of the Nazi regime because Germans would have seen them carried out.

Kershaw argues that people continued to fight when surrender would have been much more sensible for several main reasons:

    • true believers thought that Hitler had some kind of weapon about to be released, or that he would, as he had in the past, find a way to save an apparently impossible situation
    • some true believers thought that the US and UK could not keep working together and/or remain allied with the USSR, and so the alliance would crack at the crucial moment (as they believed had happened with Frederick the Great)
    • large numbers of people believed that, especially given how exterminationist their war had been, their victors would exterminate them (in other words, a kind of pro-active projection—the victors would treat the Germans as badly as the Germans had treated others)
    • large numbers of people believed they had no choice, that they would be killed or imprisoned if they did anything other than fight
    • some people were motivated by the belief that loyalty to nation is the highest value, even if the nation has been exterminationist

Notice that few of those beliefs were peculiar to Hitler, that they were rhetorically effective because they were widespread. Nazi rhetoric depended on several widespread beliefs—Nazis didn’t invent these beliefs, but relied on them:

    • the notion that Germany was entitled to European hegemony,
    • that it was “encircled” by hostile countries,
    • that it should have and could have won WWI (and was just about to)
    • when it was “stabbed in the back” by a Jewish media,
    • normalized antisemitism,
    • anti-liberalism,
    • an attraction to fascism

Prior to WWI, major German figures described what they wanted Europe to look like once they won it (which they assumed they would), and it involved every region that had German speakers as part of the German nation, and various other areas reduced to essentially client-states (that is, nations with their foreign policies dictated by Germany). That is, Europe would be dominated by Germany (the goal of German hegemony).

This domination of Europe was rationalized as a kind of pre-emptive self-defense. Germany argued that, unless it had German territory on all sides (or, at least German allies), then it was encircled by nations bent on its destruction (this is projection). That notion of every other nation either being a tool or enemy of Germany’s meant that they were necessarily headed toward war.

Many scholars have argued that, at least as far as Hitler was concerned, this perception was based on Germany seeing itself as analogous to America. The Monroe Doctrine said that the “US” was ontologically entitled to all the territory between the east and west coasts. And, so, Germans similarly felt entitled to direct control over all of central and most of eastern Europe—they saw the inhabitants of those regions the same way that many Americans in the 19th century saw the inhabitants of everything between western Ohio and eastern California (that is, as not really to be considered). America had expanded west, going to war with every nation that resisted, and so Hitler thought he could do the same east.

World War I was supposed to be a quick war, and it was thoroughly out of proportion to its apparent cause. It happened because so many countries wanted it to happen, each believing they could (and would) win it quickly and easily. France wanted to regain territory (and honor) lost in the Franco-Prussian War of 1870, Germany wanted more territory (claiming that it was victimized by “encirclement”—the fantasy that countries around it preventing expansion was somehow victimization), Austria wanted to crush opposition to its empire, Serbia wanted independence from Austria, Russia wanted to exert and demonstrate hegemony over various parts of Europe and regain honor lost in the war with Japan, Italy wanted to get recognized as a major player in European politics and get territory from Austria, England wanted to restrict German expansion. Everyone believed that the best way to gain their ends was war, and that they could win such a war quickly

Austria saw the bizarrely comical assassination of Archduke Ferdinand as an opportunity to get what it wanted in regard to Serbia, and asked if Germany would support its extraordinary demands. Germany said yes. Russia mobilized, and Germany enacted its war plan (which necessitated violating Belgian neutrality) that would, Germany thought,  mean an even cleaner and faster defeat of France than had happened in 1870. England objected to the violation of Belgian neutrality, and went to war

Germany did quite well in the war from a military perspective (as long as you ignore the relative costs of the losses), with the military dug in to safe trenches, but it couldn’t move the line of offense/defense. There were nightmarish battles over the same territory—less than a mile of ground—and Germany initiated gassing the opposition. In 1917, the Russians, whose line had collapsed, had their government collapse, which devolved into civil war and then a Marxist revolution. The Germans negotiated an extraordinarily punitive peace treaty with Russia (as they had with France in 1870), with both extraordinary demands for territory and high reparations.

On the Western Front, there was a military stalemate that significantly hurt Germany more than it hurt the Allies in two ways. First, Germany had a much more limited number of soldiers it could throw into the maw of the war. It could not win a war of attrition. Second, the Allies were effectively blockading Germany, and that meant a decreasing food supply. The German public was losing faith in what they thought was going to be a repeat of the rout that was the 1870 war. There was a last-ditch effort to reach Paris, which initially seemed effective, but failed ultimately, and then there was a break-through of what had seemed to be the impenetrable German line. And the German line collapsed, and there was open revolution in some cities in Germany. And so Germany decided to negotiate an end to the war, and, because of France, the resulting treaty was punitive (albeit no more punitive than what Germany had negotiated with France in 1870 or with Russia in 1917).

Everything about WWII is the consequence of the German perception that this treaty, the Versailles Treaty, victimized them outrageously. And while it was unhelpfully punitive, it was no worse than what they had done when they had the whip hand. And that is the rhetoric of nationalism. Is it “unfair” and “unjust” if we are treated the way we intended to treat others. It’s a kind of narcissistic foreign policy.

The Versailles Treaty was unwise, and various people recognized it would have undesirable political and economic outcomes, but the French were insistent that the Germans be treated as they had treated others. It was vengeance.

France would continue to be vengeful during the next ten years, so that their foreign policy was determined by honor and not a pragmatic concern with outcome. And here I’ll interject an editorial comment: train wrecks in public deliberation are generally associated with a community worrying more about honor than pragmatic considerations of outcome.

Germans never accepted that they were at fault for the war, because they saw the “encirclement” issue as real. They projected their own desire for European hegemony onto every other country (so, because they intended to invade every other country, they assumed that every other country intended to invade them). And they felt entitled to European hegemony, and therefore felt victimized if they couldn’t achieve it.

Antisemitism was widespread in the world, and especially in Germany (although Germany was probably not the most antisemitic European country), and it was seen as a political issue (not just racism) because, so the argument ran, the presence of large populations of Jews (especially Polish Jews) was seen as something that “weakened” Germany as a whole because, they said, 1) Jews were incapable of being really loyal to Germany (they would always value their own people more—the same argument made about the Japanese in arguments for internment); 2) Jews were inherently terrorist and communist; and 3) Jews (and various other “inferior” “races” such as the Sintis and Romas) were genetically weak, prone to disease, and inherently criminal.

There are other ways that Hitler argued he wasn’t that different from America. The Nuremburg laws weren’t that different from Jim Crow laws Nazis argued, and the US had enacted rabidly anti-Semitic immigration laws in 1924. Hitler told an American diplomat that Germany was simply making up for lost time, not having been as anti-Semitic as the US had been with the 1924 law.

The official position of the Catholic church was that Jews, although they were Christ-killers, should be tolerated, and they officially celebrated the myth of stabbing the host until the 1960s. Many Catholic media condemned Nazis on various grounds, but rarely (never?) on the grounds of Nazis being anti-Semitic.

Until the German collapse at the loss of WWI, all K-12 education in Germany was religious indoctrination. When the Democratic Socialists (that is, people who believed that public policy should be determined in a democratic way, and who thought it might be okay for the government to set limits on what businesses might do) said that religious education was not required, the Lutheran and Catholic churches fell into a faint. The SD didn’t prohibit religious education; they just didn’t require it. But not requiring that all education be religious indoctrination was, as far as Catholic and Lutheran propaganda went, victimizing religion. It was (and this is true) liberalism.

Liberalism is a vexed term, since it has always been an ultimate term. I’ll explain what the Nazis and Catholic Church meant when they condemned liberalism.

After the Enlightenment (and ignoring how the term is used in American public discourse), being “liberal” or having a “liberal” education meant that you believed:

  1. all humans are individuals, capable of individual choice, with individual rights ontologically grounded (that is, your rights are grounded in the universe itself, and not given to you by any government).
  2. those rights include freedom of conscience, meaning that the government doesn’t look into your motives—the government can set rules about how you behave, but not what you believe (this is crucial to understanding fascism, totalitarianism of various kinds—including religious–, and cults). Thus, liberalism insisted on a separation of church and state—the government can require certain behavior of you, but not require that you have specific religious beliefs. This also means that there must be a separation of public and private (there is a private realm out of which the government should stay).
  3. those rights also include due process, which means that, if you find yourself in front of a court, your case is treated in the same way that any case would be treated—so, the outcome of your case isn’t influenced by your political party, gender, sexuality, race, political party, height, choice of hat. Human rights aren’t tribal rights.
  4. people have the right to criticize the government as long as they are not inciting to riot.
  5. policy decisions should be on the basis of argumentation from different perspectives, and therefore pluralism is to be nurtured.

Authoritarians (Stalin, Hitler, Bilbo) object to every point of liberalism. They say that the true mark of nationalist loyalty is rejecting your individual identity for an experience that is simultaneously pure individuality and pure group membership. You are most purely an individual when you are a thoroughly experiencing being part of this entirely consensual group of perfect agreement. You matter when you are that group.

In an authoritarian culture, the in-group has rights, but no one else does—everyone else should be grateful that they are not more oppressed than they already are. (Also, interestingly enough, authoritarians claim to be in total control, but the narrative is that others are responsible for managing the authoritarians’ feelings—if in-group members in positions of authority are “provoked” and engage in outrageous violence, it is the fault of the “provoker.” So, they are and are not in control of their feelings. Notice this rhetoric in defenses of Nazi violence.)

The primary goal of the government in an authoritarian culture is to enforce conformity to in-group values and monovocality on in-group claims, so there is no freedom of conscience. Everyone must believe the same thing, authoritarians say, because they believe we’re weakened by pluralism.

Similarly, in-group members are essentially good, and out-group members are essentially bad (and so require more policing and punishment). In-group violence against out-group members is almost always justified (see above about provoking), but out-group violence against in-group members never is, so authoritarians see group identity as central to determining guilt. Authoritarians argue that we are always in a state of exception—the in-group is threatened with annihilation—and so due process is an unnecessary luxury. Out-group members are always already guilty of something anyway.

Only in-group members can criticize the government, and, since in-group members are loyal to the in-group, if the government is an in-group government, then criticizing the government means you’re out-group. (The “no true Scotsman” argument.)

Authoritarians generally appeal to naïve realism, and so they don’t acknowledge that multiple points of view might be valid. In an authoritarian culture, disagreement is framed as weakness, (in the sense that those who disagree are weak and trying to weaken the true believers) and so those who dissent are first shamed, then marginalized, then demonized, then excluded, then exterminated.

Authoritarian rhetoric says:

  1. A good community has no conflict. No matter how weird things might seem, there is a single right answer and the solution to our complicated issue is to find the person who can see the correct course of action (authoritarianism isn’t the only ideology that says that, but a culture based on the premise that disagreement is never genuine or beneficial generally ends up authoritarian).
  2. The person in the position of authority knows best—you know that the correct course of action is obvious, and so you just need to vote for the person who seems to understand you.

Most of the political parties in Weimar Germany were opposed to liberalism, democracy, and the very notion of pluralism. Under the Hohenzollern monarchy, what most correlates to our notion of K-12 education was religious. There was no secular education. The Social Democrats ended that monopoly, and, therefore, the major religious institutions (the Lutheran and Catholic churches) characterized the SD as evil atheists and were completely opposed to them. The Pope declared “liberalism” (and democracy) an “error” and opposition to liberalism (that is, the separation of church and state, such as allowing non-religious education) was as much a hot-button issue as abortion is in our era.

There were, loosely, six kinds of political parties:

    • rabidly anti-Semitic and xenophobic, nationalist, conservative, militarist authoritarian, fascist (most of which ended up getting enfolded into NSDAP, the Nazis);
    • anti-Semitic and xenophobic, nationalist, conservative, militarist authoritarian, pro-restoration of the monarchy (the “conservative” parties);
    • anti-Semitic, conservative, religious (such as the very powerful “Centre Party”).
    • “international socialists” (communists) who were trying to get Germany to have a Soviet-style revolution, and install a “dictatorship of the proletariat.”

Those four kinds of parties were openly and actively hostile to the very notion of democracy. There were two parties committed to democracy:

    • the “liberals” (who were conservative on many social issues);
    • social democrats (who were “socialist” in that they wanted a social safety net, but were committed to democracy—they were the dominant party through most of Weimar Germany).

Several of the parties were fascist. While “fascist” is more or less an ultimate term (meaning it’s just a way of saying “Yay!” or “Boo!”—it’s all connotation and no denotation) in common usage, among political theories, it’s much more precise. Robert Paxton identifies it in terms of its mobilizing passions (what you might call its rhetoric):

    • a sense of overwhelming crisis beyond the reach of any traditional solutions;
    • the primacy of the group, toward which one has duties superior to every right, whether individual or universal, and the subordination of the individual to it;
    • the belief that one’s group is a victim, a sentiment that justifies any action, without legal or moral limits, against its enemies, both internal and external;
    • dread of the group’s decline under the corrosive effects of individualistic liberalism, class conflict, and alien influences;
    • the need for closer integration of a purer community, by consent if possible, or by exclusionary violence if necessary;
    • the need for authority by natural leaders (always male), culminating in a national chief who alone is capable of incarnating the group’s destiny;
    • the superiority of the leader’s instincts over abstract and universal reason;
    • the beauty of violence and the efficacy of will, when they are devoted to the group’s success;
    • the right of the chosen people to dominate others without restraint from any kind of human or divine law, right being decided by the sole criterion of the group’s prowess within a Darwinian struggle. (From Anatomy of Fascism)

Notice the degree to which fascism is a rejection of liberalism—the group, not the individual matters; people don’t have rights by virtue of being human, by being good members of the right kind of group, disagreement is a vice, deliberation is unnecessary, and war is necessary.

4. Weimar Germany

Many people look back at Hitler and believe someone like him could never sucker them because, they believe, he pounded on a podium shouting for the extermination of Jews on the basis of what everyone could recognize as rabid and irrational racism. They recognize that Hitler relied on charismatic leadership, but they think they’re immune to it.

Hitler didn’t begin by arguing for extermination of the Jews. He told his audience that Germany, which should be great, was in a state of political, economic, and moral collapse because it was weakened by the presence of those people. He said we’re weakened by disagreement, and the disagreement is purely the consequence of them. He said the solutions to the major problems of the era were simple, and he could (and would) enact them immediately. Germany was trapped by procedural quibbling, “parliamentarianism” (by which he meant that everything had to be argued in the equivalent of Congress), liberals who just want to slow everything down, experts who try to tell people like you and me that our beliefs are wrong, Marxists who want to destroy what we have, and Jews who are all terrorists.

Weimar Germany was (like most of Europe) profoundly antisemitic, ranging from “they’re okay as neighbors, but I wouldn’t want my daughter o marry one” through “it sure would be nice if they all went away” to “we should kill them all.” That last group wasn’t especially large, but the other versions were widespread. (And, really, the “milder” ones could be morphed into exterminationist easily.) The Jewish stereotype (in literature, film cartoons, even songs) was that Jews were clubby, greedy, crude, and damned to Hell. Sometimes that stereotype was presented as though it were positive (G.K. Chesterton’s antisemitism fits into this category, and Wyndham Lewis’ Are Jews Human is another apt example).

Many people decide that a claim is true if it’s repeated in their informational world a lot, and if it’s repeated by people they respect. If a claim is unanimously supported by their ingroup and contested by one of their outgroups, many people will decide it must be true (a version of social knowing). Basically, this whole long discussion of Hitler could be compressed in my saying that that way of approaching decisions is what enabled Hitler (and Stalin), and so anyone who approaches decisions that way doesn’t get to pretend s/he would have recognized Hitler or Stalin as evil. Nope. Congratulations: if you reason that way about politics, here is your death’s head symbol!

Karl Marx was Jewish, and many of the people in Lenin’s close circle were Jewish, and a lot of anti-Semitic propaganda equated being Jewish and being Bolshevik. Of course, most Jews weren’t Bolshevik, and not all Bolsheviks were Jews, but people engage in very sloppy reasoning when it comes to an outgroup. Since we have a tendency to assume the outgroup is essentially evil, then the bad behavior of some of them seems to typify all of them. By the early twentieth century most of the major financiers were not Jewish, but the Rothschild family came to be the symbol of international finance.

Thus, a large number of people were willing to blame Jews for Bolshevism, capitalism, the loss of WWI, entry into WWI, and anything else that needed a scapegoat. Sometimes that stereotype was presented by an author as though it wasn’t unreasonable—a hero or narrator might grant that not all Jews were involved in a worldwide conspiracy, but assert that all conspiracies were Jewish (an assumption so widespread that it amounted to a cliche in thrillers).  A fair number of people also blamed Jews for draining blood from Christian boys, killing Jesus (a particularly pernicious claim), stealing consecrated hosts. Many people, especially those who had made it through the near Soviet-style revolts in some German cities https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/German_Revolution_of_1918%E2%80%9319, were deeply opposed to Soviet-style communism (a not unreasonable concern) but a lot of anti-communist propaganda equated Bolshevism (as it was called) and Jews. https://muse.jhu.edu/book/8930 It’s important to understand that connection, otherwise it’s easy to miss why Nazism was so successful.

Jews were thoroughly marginalized in Czarist Russia, and, so, compared to the number of Jews in the general population, it could be argued that there was a disproportionate number of Jews in Lenin’s immediate circle. He also had a disproportionate number of close advisors from Georgia, and no one wonders about the disproportionate number of New Yorkers in the official and unofficial cabinet of a New York President. We expect that people will rely heavily and work with people in their social circle; if that circle is marked by ougroup membership (especially by race or religion) then we decide there is a causal correlation. Since Jews were marked as outgroup, then the Jewishness of any participant in Lenin’s revolution or cabinet was marked and assumed to have some kind of causal relationship to Bolshevism.

Here’s one way to think about that. If a person wearing a t-shirt showing they support a politician, religion, or sports team you loathe treats you badly in line at the grocery store, you’ll attribute their being a jerk to their being in your outgroup. They did that jerky thing because they’re Wisconsin Synod Lutherans, and we all know how they are. That incident will confirm your sense that Wisconsin Synod Lutherans are inherently evil. If someone behaved exactly the same way but had a t-short that showed they shared some kind of identity important to you, if you are Wisconsin Synod Lutheran, then you would attribute their behavior to something else (they’re wearing someone else’s shirt, they’re having a bad day). Unhappily, therefore, a depressing number of people who self-identified as Christian equated “Jewish” with “atheist Bolshevism” (the same way that many people now equate “Muslim” with “politically motivated terrorists”).

Thus, in Weimar Germany, many people were willing to believe that Bolshevism was Jewish, and while people were willing to grant that not all Jews were Bolshevists, they believed that enough of them were that the entire “race” (and keep in mind, Judaism isn’t a race) should be removed from Germany. It was the peanut analogy—if you know that some peanuts are poison, you would throw out the whole bowl, or at least keep more from entering.

Let’s be clear: the attempt to “cleanse” Europe of all sorts of identities (Jews, Romas, Sintis, Poles, intellectuals, Marxists, union leaders, liberals, homosexuals) began as an argument that was framed as “it’s best for all of us if they go elsewhere.”

Hitler’s policies regarding stigmatized groups could be framed as reasonable throughout his career. Initially, his claim was that Germany needed to protect itself against parasites (takers), immigrants, peoples not capable of being really German, groups that were inherently criminal, his political opponents, and that meant more purity in the culture, more rigidactions on the part of police, less concern about due process and fairness, and a more open equation of German-ness and a particular political group.

Hitler persuaded a large number of people that he was them, that he cared about them, and they needed to throw all their faith onto him, and he persuaded others (who were appalled at the liberalism of Weimar Germany) that he was their only choice to undo the liberal policies of Weimar politics. Many people voted for him for those reasons, even ones really uncomfortable with his tendency to engage in bigoted claims about various races and religions. They believed that democracy was dead, as was shown by the inability of the Weimar democracy to make the situation better (it actually had done a pretty good job, but the main problem was thatcompromise and deliberation were demonized, but that’s a tangent I’ll avoid).

My point is that Hitler’s genocidal policies wouldn’t have seemed to his audience as purely racial; it would have seemed to his audience as though the groups he was targeting really were political and economic threats. A lot of people really did believe that Jews were intent on imposing communism everywhere and they could name acts of terrorism and revolution in which Jews participated, and they could point to all sorts of media, common discourse, and “walking down the street” experience to say that some groups are just useless takers—Polack jokes, getting “gypped” by someone.

There were terrorists who were Jewish; there were criminals who were Sintis. Therefore, “normal” people could “know” that a group of Jews or Romas would include terrorists and criminals, and so they defined the essence of Jews and Romas as terrorist and criminal. Germany had a lot of terroristic violence, with a lot of it (most?) committed by Nazis and other volkisch groups. But many people wrote off that violence as either justified (as self-defense against the Jews) or inessential. The US, right now, has a lot of terrorism, most of it committed by white males who self-identify as Christian. Yet, how many people worried about terrorism are worried about white male Christians? They engage in the no true Scotsman defense, and only worry about outgroup violence, and, as too many people in Weimar Germany did, they are willing to generalize about the essence of another religion, while engaging in considerable cognitive work to keep from admitting that most terrorism is ingroup.

I’m not saying that the Jews of the 1917-1933 are in every way like Muslims of 1996-now, or “the Mexicans” in current discourse, or “the Japs” in the first half of the twentieth century, the Irish, Germans, Poles, and Italians in the nineteenth century, the Poles and Italians until the mid-century, the Native Americans from the first European landing until the 1980s. I’m not saying that every immigrant group is in every way the same; I’m saying that the rhetoric about every immigrant group is the same.

And, in regard to every immigrant group, a person who wanted to say this group is bad could find evidence to support that claim. Every immigrant group has a rosy picture of what their immigrant ancestors were like, and is appalled by what this immigrant group looks like, because these immigrants trouble the rosy picture. It’s never about this immigrant group (which isn’t any different from any other)—anti-immigrant rhetoric is persuasive precisely because descendants of immigrants want to believe that their ancestors weren’t like this group. But they were.

If you believe that this group of immigrants is bad, you can find evidence to support that belief. If you compare your daily interaction with this set of immigrants to your narrative about your immigrant ancestors, then you are comparing your daily interaction with your family tradition. That narrative is falsifiable. You could look into the very clear data about your ancestors and find that all the arguments you’re making about this group apply to your ancestors.

But, very few people do that. We don’t tend to reason in ways that involve falsifiability. We tend to engage in motivated reasoning, a process whereby we use all our powers of reasoning to support the beliefs we already have.

Imagine that you have been presented with a claim. How do you decide if it is true or false?

    • you can ask yourself whether it fits with what you already believe;
    • you can ask yourself whether the support for this claim is support you would think valid if presented for a claim that doesn’t fit what you believe.

Injustice happens because people start with a claim and look for reasons to support it. And they can always find those reasons. Rhetoric provides the reasons—that is, the topoi or talking points.

Rhetoric, when it’s seen as a process of reasoning, and not just a way to get others to do what you want, can be a way of getting people to the second way of thinking about decision-making. And, if a community is oriented toward thinking about decisions that way—not just, “can I find evidence for my claim” but “are my ways of arguing ways I would think legitimate if people I hate used them”—then injustice is a little bit harder rhetorically. So, in this class, I want to argue that we need to pay attention to that second kind of rhetoric—rhetoric as a method of self-reflection.

I’m making a claim about how people in a moment understand things, and if they’re operating within the first model of reasoning (a claim is true if I can find a reason to support it), then their method of reasoning largely depends on the media they consume. In Weimar Germany, a time of highly factionalized media, people were really worried because of events that had actually happened (the communist uprisings, the loss of the war, the collapse of the front), but also ones that hadn’t (desecrations of the host, Jews having killed Jesus, the stab in the back),  but they decided the communist uprisings, failure of the military, loss of faith in the war were not the consequence of Germany’s commitment to European hegemony, militarism, and contempt for other nations. Germany hadn’t been wrong to go to war; it was the REAL victim here.

Germany invaded Belgium (and thereby started WWI) because, on the whole, Germans believed they were entitled to be the dominant power in Europe, they were entitled to huge amounts of territory not at that moment German, and they could easily and quickly win in a war against Russia, France, and England.

When that isn’t how things played out, German politicians all adopted the popular narrative—that Germany was the REAL victim, that it had been robbed of victory, that Germany had done nothing wrong in anything it did in regard to WWI.

Weimar Germany was a democracy in which only two of the dominant six political positions supported the concept of democracy, in which any political figure who said that perhaps rabid nationalism, German exceptionalism, and plans for European hegemony might be bad had no political chance, and in which four of the dominant political alignments said that anything to their left was Bolshevik. It was a world in which Germany’s situation couldn’t be debated because any self-criticism was off the table.

Hitler accepted a narrative about civilization and race that was popular in some circles and also accepted among many experts (especially the new science of genetics). The idea was that evolution is progressive, so that a “more evolved” species is better in every way than a less evolved one (Gould’s Mismeasure of Man remains a really good introduction to all that discourse, even with some disagreements as to his argument on brain size measurements). In this view, “immorality” is more common among “lower” species, so that higher animals (like humans) behave in a more moral way than lower animals (like apes). In addition, dominant genetics said that there were sometimes “throwbacks” in evolution (called atavism), so that humans are sometimes born with characteristics genetically connected to earlier (and lower) stages in our evolution, such as babies born with tails. Races, many of these people argued, functioned as species, and so there are races that are closer to animals, and they are more inherently criminal, and essentially incapable of autonomy. This version of genetics was simultaneously deeply flawed and very popular. And it’s important to understand both parts to understand Hitler’s popularity.

Since morality is just as much genetic as a tail, this argument ran, and the more genetically advanced are more moral, then immorality is also an evolutionary throwback. Groups that are more immoral are more like animals in every way, and it’s because of their genetics.

The last bad idea in this cornucopia of bad ideas is that we should think about human genetics the way we think about breeding racehorses, bunnies, or chickens. Notice that throughout this discussion I haven’t defined “morality,” nor terms like “higher” or “better.” Here I’m following how geneticists wrote–they began their research by assuming that there was perfect agreement on those terms, and thereby enabled themselves not to see the circularity in their arguments. Most people charged with crimes were recent immigrants or criminalized ethnicities, and, since crime is immoral, they concluded that those ethnicities were genetically criminal. (We still make this mistake, by assuming that rates of arrest are perfect representations of rates of commission of crime.)

So, what they didn’t notice in their own research was that their own standards of “better” were actually pretty odd. They tended to equate, without noticing, market value with better. A racehorse is “better” than a drafthorse insofar as you pay more for the former than the latter, but a racehorse is a terrible draft horse. To get the fastest horse, breeding two fast horses is a good choice, but a fast horse is not always the better horse. The research on chickens and bunnies is unintentionally hilarious (with horror about the monstrosity of a bunny with one ear upright and the other floppy). It’s also contradictory, since, as mentioned above, market value was often taken as a pure measure of goodness, and market value is often enhanced by genetic oddities. Or, in other words, purebred, and inbred are pretty similar, as shown in the Hapsburg Jaw. https://www.livescience.com/3504-inbreeding-downfall-dynasty.html  I love Great Danes, and even I will admit that a purebred Great Dane is not a better dog than a mutt–it’s much more likely to have terrible problems. But early twentieth-century genetics assumed that purity is always better, except when it didn’t.

What’s odd to a rhetorician about the genetics rhetoric is that it was so obviously wrong, even in its era. Anthropologists, linguists, and even a lot of biologists took issue with geneticists’ arguments in the first decade of the 20th century (that’s why geneticists had to form their own organizations–they couldn’t stand the critiques). Anyone familiar with the Habsburgs knew purity wasn’t good, and genetics simultaneously assumed that purity was better AND condemned inbreeds like the Jukes family.

Early twentieth century genetics was just a muck of contradictory assumptions. For instance, it was a convention to say that a cross between a higher and lower was halfway between the two, but, of course, even royal families had their “lower” babies–epileptics, hemophiliacs, homosexuals. And anyone even a little familiar with breeding dogs or horses knew that not only did you often get a dud from two great individuals, but that there were always surprises from less than stellar lines. That it was muddled is an important point, because when a particular sustained conversation (that is, a bunch of people who have created a kind of argumentative ingroup—a subreddit, Fox News, DailyKos, analytic philosophers, native plant gardeners—sometimes called a “discourse community”) have an argument that doesn’t have internally consistent arguments, then you know you’ve got an ideologically-driven discourse community.

That point might seem a little pedantic, and it’s important for understanding when the Hitler analogy is and isn’t relevant, so I should explain it a little more. In rhetoric, it’s common to talk about enclaves, which are little safe spaces in which like-minded people can huddle together and do nothing but agree how awesome they all are.

Enclaves are great, and we all need them, and so every life should have at least one. Enclaves are places where we all agree, and we go to feel that we are part of a group that is entirely right, and entirely good, and entirely powerful.

Enclaves are useful for motivation, and, really, it’s just lovely to be in an enclave. Everything is clear, and everything is comfortable and no one will tell you  that you might have fucked up.

Enclaves can be politically important. Lefty women relegated to making coffee and working the mimeograph literally got together and discovered they all shared similar experiences. Our Bodies, Our Selves came out of an enclave. The Tea Party is an enclave-based movement, as was Earth First. Within your enclave, deciding that loyalty to that group is important makes perfect sense. The institutional goal of an enclave is to make people feel safe within a group. Enclaves are also good for motivation—before putting on a show, or playing a competitive sport, and in those circumstances it wouldn’t be helpful for someone to say, “Well, maybe the other team is better, and really should win.”

But all the research on decision-making is clear that it isn’t good for a large institution or community to make decisions from within an enclave, largely because of that enclave emphasis on loyalty to the group being such a high value. Good decisions require good disagreement, and criticism of the ingroup is generally perceived as disloyalty. And, so, while it’s common for political agenda to be brainstormed within an enclave, and it’s healthy for all of us to retreat to one from time to time, political agenda should be subject to criticism, worst-case scenario thinking, assessment of weaknesses and challenges, and honest assessments of previous failures. So, at some point, that political agenda needs to be shared outside of an enclave.

Determining processes and policies within an enclave is challenging, because of the value on loyalty, and so it’s common for enclaves either to splinter into sub-communities on which everyone agrees, or to begin threatening dissenters with violence and exclusion. Unhappily, the more that an enclave values loyalty, the more likely it is to devolve into smaller communities, or become a community in which people can’t disagree.

Genetics ended up being an enclave expert discourse. Instead of respond to the serious objections and criticism of eugenics made by contemporaries, they created their own journals and departments (and as in the case of Franz Boas, tried to get really threatening critics fired). And what eugenics had to say could be defended with complicated charts and statistics (which was a relatively new field at that point), and it confirmed everyday and very popular racism. But it was popular, and it was powerful–even college textbooks endorsed it. That science was used to rationalize the US forced sterilization of 60k people, the extraordinarily restrictive 1924 Immigration Act, Japanese internment, anti-Asian immigration/naturalization rules and statutes, antimiscegenation laws, and segregation in the US. Every claim of that kind of genetics was rejected by methodologically sound research in anthropology, linguistics, and biology, but my point is that it was easy for racists to find apparently expert support for their racist policies (see Science for Segregation).

The most problematic claims of eugenics were that “race” is a biological category (the history of debates over “whiteness” show that isn’t true); that races exist on a hierarchy of civilization (some races are essentially more gifted with intelligence, morality, strength, and all the virtues that merit higher status and pay–other races are given the virtues, such as being good with children, that are connected to lower status and pay); that the “mixing” of races results in children who are closer to the “lower” than the “higher” race; and that the “white” race (sometimes Nordic, sometimes Aryan) is responsible for all the great civilizations in the history of humanity, and those civilizations fail when the white/Nordic/Aryan race stops being pure. Race-mixing, these people say, weaken civilizations. Hitler used this narrative to argue that “lesser” races had to be exterminated, and that punishing ‘race-mixing’ with death was justified. Even after the war, supporters of segregation cited the same shitty “science” that justified Hitler’s genocide–that line of argument figured into the lower courts’ rulings on Loving v. Virginia in the 60s.

So, while we look back at Hitler’s racism and see it as insane, and while the most methodologically sound scholarship of the era had long since shown it to be ideologically driven, people who wanted to believe that some racial groups were inherently more dangerous, more criminal, more prone to terrorism, more genetically driven to be poor could find experts who would tell them that they were right. Hell, they could find entire departments at some universities who would tell them that.

What made Hitler’s “science” bad wasn’t that it now looks bad to us, nor that it was a fringe science, nor that it didn’t have supporting evidence—it did. What made it bad was the logic of their arguments—their failure to define terms, to put forward internally consistent arguments, and to define the conditions that would falsify their claims. For instance, eugenicists never came up with a definition of “race” that they used consistently—sometimes they meant nationality, sometimes language group, sometimes, as in the case of “the Jews,” they talked about a religion as though it were a race (the same thing is happening now with people whorefer to the “Muslim race” or who assume that “Muslim” and “Arabic” are the same).

In Germany, the “science” was slightly different, as was the religious rhetoric. In the US, there was a lot of support for “science” that said that African Americans, Latinx, Native Americans, and Asians deserved their economic, political, and cultural situation because it was the natural situation. In Germany, there wasn’t as much political need to rationalize the oppression of African Americans, Latinx, Native Americans, or Asians, but Jews, Sintis, Romas, various central and eastern European groups filled that same role, and there was the same rhetorical need to naturalize their oppression. Hitler’s long-term plan was to establish the same kind of plantation system in eastern Europe that England had in places like Rhodesia (Kershaw’s biographies of Hitler are especially good on this).

Although he called himself national socialist (meaning not the international socialists–that is, Marxist socialism), what he meant was European colonialism. In his era “socialism” meant redistribution of wealth, and he imagined a racial redistribution of wealth. Central and eastern Europe would become the Rhodesia of Germany. So, once Europe was Jew-free, then the other lesser races would behave in the ways British colonialism used Africans. Poles, for instance, would act as workers, perhaps even managers, for the large estates run by Aryans.

Hitler’s plans were more extreme that most of the dominant rhetoric of the era (which was still pretty racist), and so he was clever about keeping it out of the larger public sphere. But he meant it, as is shown by his deliberations with his generals (a different post entirely). Briefly, his military decisions were grounded in his understandings of races, and since his understandings of race were wrong, they were bad decisions. Again, that’s a different post (involving the Hitler Myth).

For this course, what matters is that German (European, to be blunt) cultural rhetoric provided a lot of support for essentializing the evil of those groups (lefties, homosexuals, Sintis anbd Romas, union leaders, Jews, Jehovah’s Witnesses, “mentally retarded”) because that rhetoric assumed that there was a clear distinction between “them” and “us” and that the differences were biological (that is, grounded in genes and incapable of genuine change).

But, as in the US, while people would support the lynching here and there of outgroup members, disproportionate incarceration rates, polite racism (social exclusion, racist employment practices, shunning people in intergroup marriages), the same people who believed that that group is essentially evil balked at government-sponsored violence in front of their eyes (Hitler, the Germans, and the Final Solution is elegant on this). Prior to the war, most Germans didn’t want all the Jews in Europe to be killed, and they probably wouldn’t have supported Hitler in 1933 had he said that was what he would do. But he didn’t say it, and they supported his putting in place the systems, policies, and processes (especially one-party government, an openly politicized and authoritarian police force, and personal loyalty to him being the central value—more on all those below), because they were okay with the kind of expulsions and restrictions they thought Hitler had in mind for those kind of scary Others.

I’ve given so much background on eugenics/genetics because I think that one mistake that people make when they think they would recognize Hitler and resist (or believe that comparing their beloved authoritarian to Hitler is a ridiculous analogy) is that they think Hitler started off by calling for genocide based on wacky science. He didn’t initially explicitly call for genocide (or, at least, people didn’t hear him saying that, and he gave himself a lot of plausible deniability), and most of his intended audience wouldn’t have seen the science as wacky.

So, when we’re worried about whether this leader is like Hitler in troubling ways, we shouldn’t be looking for someone who will use early-twentieth century genetics to argue for exterminating Jews. We also shouldn’t be looking for someone who will cite obviously whackjob “science” or fringe experts to support the bizarre notions of some marginalized group. We should worry more about a leader who is citing experts whose “science” can’t withstand the rigors of academic argument, who have had to form their own journals and organizations, but whose claims are attractive both to authoritarian leaders and to most people because they confirm common beliefs. The most important failure of those experts (and the propaganda supporting and promoting them) is that neither they nor their supporters can make arguments that are both internally consistent and apply the same rhetorical/logical standards across groups.

It’s also important to understand that German media was rabidly factional—you only read a paper that supported your political views. There was, therefore, considerable inoculation. Rhetorical inoculation is crucial to understanding how authoritarianism works. Just as giving someone cowpox (a weak version of smallpox) will enable them to resist smallpox if they encounter it, so presenting a person with a weak version of an ideology can enable their cognitive system to reject any argument of that ideology, even much stronger versions. While that might be useful for immunology, it is profoundly anti-democratic in that the whole point of it is to persuade citizens not to listen to anyone who disagrees. It says that you already know what they’re going to say, and it’s stupid. When it works, citizens don’t know any points of view other than their own, but they think they do, and so they’re making uninformed decisions while thinking they’re as informed as they need to be.

Inoculation ensures that we have a citizenry that is simultaneously un- and mis-informed about their policy options.

Imagine, for the sake of argument, that your political party has proposed exterminating squirrels. Until this point you might not have felt strongly about squirrels, but you do feel strongly about your identification with that party. What social psychologists call “motivated reasoning” will kick in. Instead of trying to determine the various options we have in regard to squirrels, your loyalty to your party means that you will be motivated to find ways to support the position being loyal means. Your skills of reasoning will be put purely to the use of making your party’s stance comfortable. (If you’re very loyal, then you might even persuaded yourself you’ve always hated squirrels.)

And why is your party advocating the extermination of squirrels? If they were really worried about squirrels’ eating birdseed, then they might cosider other policies, especially since rats and grackels also eat birdseed (in fact, so does one of my dogs). Thus, they would have a complicated policy. If, however, they are interested in using the issue of squirrels eating birdseed to further a different agenda, or they wanted to use it just to rouse passionate support for the party, or distract from other issues, or as a wedge issue–basically, if they’re doing all sorts of things other than trying to solve the birdseed problem, they’ll have a simple policy and most of their rhetoric will be fear and hate mongering about squirrels and anyone who isn’t supporting extermination.

When that us vs. them rhetoric (demagoguery) works, it does so by persuading people to refuse to look at the opposition arguments, or even ingroup criticism of the party policy. It says, “Anyone who disagrees with us is pro-squirrel, and that means that they want squirrels to take over the world.”

Authoritarianism works by saying there are two choices: our good set of policies (our ingroup) and everything else, and those two choices are obviously between what is good (rational, moral, clear) and what is bad (irrational, immoral, relativist). Authoritarianism works when it persuades people to make decisions on the basis of group identity. Authoritarianism also always says that the situation of the ingroup is so disastrous that we don’t have time for deliberation. In Robert Paxton’s words, we are in an “overwhelming crisis beyond the reach of traditional solutions.”

In authoritarianism, the goal is not just inoculation against their arguments, but also against democratic deliberation generally.

Hitler said: We are not in a bad situation because of having made bad decisions in the past. WWI didn’t start because of Germany having decided to support Austria in a stupid bluff, and our invading Belgium was the fault of England, and it had nothing to do with nationalism and racism about the French and a political system that put too much power in the hands of an individual who might have poor judgment. We’re the real victims here. The Versailles Treaty is evil (and let’s not talk about the conditions imposed on France after the Franco-Prussian War of 1870), and we only lost WWI because of Jews (who are all Bolshevists, especially the capitalists, and who are sort of a race and sort of a religion, and don’t ask too much about that or the whole capitalist/communist thing).

For much of Hitler’s audience, that was tl;dr.

What he said was: you’re in a bad situation; it can’t be your fault. You’re a German, so it can’t be Germany’s fault. IT’S THE LIBERALS. Who are Jews. And Bolsheviks. And international financiers. ALL TRUE GERMANS AGREE. Our government sucks because it isn’t giving you the things you know you deserve, and it isn’t dominating every other country, and GOD WANTS US TO BE THE BEST, and democracy involves letting other people argue and they’re all wrong and so it’s a waste of time because the true course of action is obvious to every reasonable person and so ELECT SOMEONE WHO CARES ABOUT PEOPLE LIKE YOU. And who will insist that GERMANY IS THE BEST. A strong man who will just walk into every international negotiation and dominate everyone and insist that they submit to Germany and send our kickass military into any country or region that disagrees is the right person for foreign policy. As far as domestic policies, we need someone who gets people like us, who cares about us. Politicians who say it’s complicated are just trying to line their own pockets. Democratic deliberation is a waste of time–just hand over all the power to a guy who can get things done. And that’s me.

The fact is that that kind of political rhetoric never ends well, but it always looks as though it will. And it looks as though it will work out okay because it appeals to the sense that people like us are good, and so things that people like us support must be good.

I’m trying to make two points here: first, no one supports genocide or world war at the beginning. We end up in genocide or world war because we don’t think about the logic of the policies we’re supporting, about the long-term and possibly inevitable consequences. Second, Hitler’s success came about because he depoliticized politics–he said it wasn’t about political issues, but about whether he was the kind of person people could trust, and therefore they should hand all decisions over to him.

Although Germany had (at least) six political parties, there was a strong tendency, especially among the conservatives, to break it into three: Bolsheviks (they included Democratic Socialists in this category, although the SD were Marxians opposed to Stalinism, and who were not arguing for a violent revolution); conservatives, and the fringe nationalist authoritarians like the Nazis. So, because they insisted that the SD were Bolsheviks, the Nazis looked like a better choice. Had the conservatives been willing to work with the SD, Hitler would never have happened.[17]

People were persuaded to support Hitler because they believed, deep into their bones, that Social Democrats were bad—because they thought Social Democrats would engage in too much governmental control of businesses, damage the standing of churches, promote secular education, tolerate homosexuality, allow divorce, allow abortion, allow birth control. And, yes, the Social Democrats would have done all of that. But they weren’t Bolsheviks, and the conservatives couldn’t admit that. And, so, conservatives supported a party that controlled businesses far more than the Social Democrats would have, tanked the autonomy of churches, again, far more than the Social Democrats would have, taught a religion of one party in schools, killed homosexuals, promoted race-based divorce, and banned abortion for Aryans, while promoting it for inferior races. And, just to top it all off, started a war that split Germany, helped Bolshevik Russia more than the SD ever would have, guaranteed the Cold War, devastated the German economy, caused the devastation of German cities, and killed 60 million people.

Because conservatives couldn’t think reasonably about the Social Democrats, they caused all that. The devastation isn’t all on Hitler; it’s more on the people whose irrational terror about compromise with Social Democrats meant they supported Nazis. Although Hitler was a great public speaker, he was only effective when the historical moment was right. Yet, by the end of the war, Germans had been persuaded to do things they would never have done in 1932.

These, then, are the four questions this course will pursue:

    • if Germans were persuaded to do or believe things they wouldn’t previously have done or believed, what caused those changes?
    • what did Hitler’s rhetoric actually do?
    • is rhetoric morally neutral and ethical or unethical only on the basis of the rhetor’s goals? In rhetoric, do the ends justify the means?
    • finally when, rhetorically, is the comparison to Hitler a useful and productive move in an argument?

[1] There are various versions. This one is from here: https://www.ushmm.org/wlc/en/article.php?ModuleId=10007392

[2] Throughout this book, I talk about people as the agents and objects of persuasion, but, of course, that isn’t really the case—there are many circumstances in which non-humans are agents and/or objects of persuasion, such as when I try to get my dog to leave my shoes alone, or my dog tries to get me to play. For purposes of this book, it’s stylistically more straightforward to talk about people, so that’s what I’ll do.

[3] There is considerable scholarly debate as to exactly when and why he came to believe that those should be the goals of himself and Germany, and he did vary as to which policies or political strategies would best achieve those goals, such as the question of at what moment he decided on the physical extermination of the Jews, but his goal of a Germany with no Jews was clearly stated early on.

[4] Germany’s exceptionalism was a necessary consequence of fascist eschatology.

[5] And, because it’s nonsense, people lose faith in persuasion and argumentation. But it’s like concluding that antibiotics are useless for curing an infection because one insufficient dose of the wrong (and expired) antibiotic didn’t cure a major infection.

[6] You’ll read about Hitler’s plans for Poland later in the class. Briefly, he intended to eradicate Polish cultural through a kind of classicide—exterminating all the Polish elite–, turn the best agricultural areas over to Germans, and turn the indigenous peoples into slaves.

[7] Sometimes standardized tests have questions that assume binary paired terms. You might get something that asks, “ducks are to birds as bunnies are to….” but that isn’t assuming the paired terms are binary. It isn’t assuming that all animals are either birds or mammals. If someone were to use that set of paired terms to argue that flies must be birds because they aren’t mammals, then you’d have binary paired terms.

[8] There’s really interesting research that people who believe this—that the only proof that a claim is true is that it seems true to them—are more easily suckered, less likely to admit error, and more likely to claim they never believed the false thing when they did (some of this is summarized in Tetlock).

[9] This move—it’s only bad when the out-group does it—is often condemned as hypocrisy, but it really isn’t. The person condemning Hubert and defending Chester isn’t pretending to have values they don’t; they are clear that their values are to defend Chester, and that they hold Chesterians and Hubertians to different standards because they believe the same behavior means different things. Chesterians are inherently good, and so their bad behavior is just a one-off and irrelevant distraction, but bad behavior on the part of Hubertians is proof of their essentially bad nature. This way of arguing is a logical error, and not a question of pretense.

[10] Scholars in rhetoric use the term dissociation in a very different way from how it’s used in psychology, so don’t get confused. In rhetoric, it’s used for breaking an action or concept into two, often on a real v. apparent basis. It might look as though Eichmann was a racist, since he was engaged in racist actions, but, he argued, he wasn’t really racist because reasons. (He was racist, by the way.)

[11] The exception may be the kind of indoctrination that happens in cult situations, but even that kind of rhetorical relationship has limits. For more on how persuasion works, see Alexandra Stein, Terror, Love, and Brainwashing.

[12] Here I want to set aside the really complicated question of what makes a disagreement productive, and just say that I don’t necessarily mean one in which someone persuades the other—sometimes a disagreement in which we fail to reach consensus is good, because we understand one another better, or we’ve become less certain about our own positions, or groundwork has been laid for persuasion down the road. And, if I persuade you to do something really harmful to you or our community, that isn’t necessarily a productive conversation.

[13] The various factors that contribute to intransigence on a point include: a lack of trust between us (I don’t think you’re a trustworthy person, and so I won’t believe anything you say), I’m deeply committed to my position due to various factors (including that I’ve talked about it a lot in public, it’s an important talking-point for my in-group, my commitment to this belief has caused me to injure someone, I believe that I am someone who always already knows the truth and changing my mind would be a weakness, the position you’re offering frightens me for some reason.

[14] One of the ways that cults ensure conformity of belief is to make people completely dependent on the cult—financially, spiritually, and emotionally—by getting members to cut off or minimize contact with others (abusive partners or parents do this too). Once they’ve been cut off, then members have a hard time dissenting since dissent might mean expulsion, and expulsion seems unthinkable because they have no support structures (economic or emotional) outside of the abusive relationship.

[15]Frans H. Van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst http://www.ditext.com/eemeren/pd.html Published in Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings, edited by Hans V. Hansen and Robert C. Pinto (1995).

[16] Once you’ve learned policy argumentation, you’ll be shocked how rarely people argue solvency—they’ll often either simply assert it, or else they’ll show that the plan solves a need other than the one they argued was present. For instance, if I argue that you need to get better grades in classes, and then I argue for the plan of your tap-dancing down Guadalupe every day, then providing evidence it will help you get dates, my solvency and need arguments don’t match.

[17] There was an actually communist—that is, Stalinist—political party, and they were generally not willing to work with the SD and never with the conservatives. Many of them believed that electing someone like Hitler would make things so bad that there would be a people’s revolution. Whether Hitler would have been prevented had they been more willing to compromise is something people still argue about.

Table of Contents for Hitler and Rhetoric coursepack

Table of contents for the Rhetoric and Hitler course.

This coursepack is in addition to the required texts.

Required texts: Hitler, Mein Kampf (required)

Gregor, How to Read Hitler (recommended)

Evans, The Coming of the Third Reich (required)

                                    The Third Reich in Power (recommended)

Ullrich, Hitler (required)

coursepack at Jenn’s (required)

Jasinski, Sourcebook (available as an e-book through the UT   Library)

 

Syllabus

Rhetoric and Hitler: an introduction

Kenneth Buke, “Rhetoric of Hitler’s ‘Battle’”

O’Shaughnessy, from Selling Hitler

McElligott, from Rethinking Weimar Germany

Hitler, March 23, 1933 speech

Sample papers

“Advice on Wrting”

Hitler, speech to the NSDAP 9/13, 1937

—. speech, 8/22/39

—. interview with Johst

—. speech, 1/27/32

Tourish and Vatcha, “Charismatic Leadership and Corporate Cultism at Enron: The Elimination of Dissent, the Promotion of Conformity and Organizational Collapse”

Entry on interpellation

Hitler, speech 4/28/39

Selection from Hitler’s Table Talk (480-83)

Kershaw, from The End (386-400)

Hitler, speech 7/13/34

Longerich, selection from Holocaust (Nazi evolution on genocide)

Selection from Hitler’s Table Talk 12-16, 422-426

Entry on inoculation

Selection from Tapping Hitler’s Generals (30-62)

Kershaw, from Hitler, The Germans, and the Final Solution (197-206)

Selection from Mayer, They Thought They Were Free (166-173)

“Dog whistle politics”

Selections from Shirer’s radio broadcasts

Selection from Snyder’s Black Earth

Selection from Hitler’s Table Talk (75-79)

Selection from Spicer’s Antisemitism, Christian Ambivalence, and the Holocaust

Hitler, speech 4/12/22

“Dissociation” from Perelman and Olbrecths-Tyteca’s The New Rhetoric

Selection from Encyclopedia of Rhetoric

Selection from Eichmann in Jerusalem

Selection from Eichmann Interrogated

Selection from Hitler and His Generals

Selection from Ordinary Men

Louis Goldblatt’s testimony before the Committee on National Defense Migration

Letter to Mr. Monk

Thomas Mann, “That Man is My Brother”

“Masculinity and Nationalism”

“Art of Masculine Victimhood”

Hitler, speech 6/22/41

selection from Longerich’s Hitler

selection from Maschmann’s Account Rendered

 

Arguing against injustice: Louis Goldblatt before the Tolan Committee

In 1942, after years of fear-mongering about “the Japanese,” the US was seriously considering race-based mass imprisonment of legal aliens and citizens of Japanese ethnicity. The Tolan Committee was formed by a progressive Congressman to have hearings on the West Coast about whether such imprisonment (euphemistically called “evacuation”) should happen. Louis Goldblatt, representing the California State Industrial Union Council, was one of few people to do a fiery anti-imprisonment speech. This is the record of the speech.

       

How we got Pearl Bailey

When Marquis died, I thought I didn’t want a dog for several weeks, but, it is summer, and I’m home more (so Jim isn’t entirely in charge of doggie daycare), and Jacob said he’d like us to get a dog while he’s home, and Clarence cannot be left alone. Jim and I, having been through so many health and behavioral problems with rescue dogs (although some, like Chester, George, and Marquis, were fine) thought we might reward ourselves for almost thirty years of rescue with one dog from a reputable breeder. That would take months.

And, I thought, we could look.

Because Clarence can get grumpy with other dogs, we were clear we needed a puppy. We planned out a day of looking at puppies—there were four sites that we found had adoptions going on. So, Jacob, Jim, and I planned out our route and, as we were heading out, the idea came up of stopping off at Phydeaux (a nearby independently owned pet store). They often have adoption events on weekends, and they might have good advice for where we should go (or if there are reputable backyard breeders in the area—a true unicorn). We walked in and there were some people with puppies!

They were all small breeds—way too small for Clarence (who genuinely doesn’t know what his back end is doing). We told the person  in charge that our fifteen year old dog had died the previous week, that we are good with big dogs, and that we couldn’t take a little one because we had a rescue mastiff at home. And she pulled out her phone and showed us an Anatolian Shepherd/Great Pyrenees mix that was, at that point on the south side of Austin. Each of us looked at the picture, looked at each other, and then looked at the woman. She persuaded us to fill out an adoption form immediately, called that location, discovered there was someone there who wanted the puppy, and said, “Tell them they’re fallback.”

She wanted us to have that puppy. So, we filled out the form, and she was talking about how she could get us the dog today if we had proof of various things (such as our dogs’ being spayed or neutered). And we drove to the south of Austin, and went into the store that had Pearl, and explained we were the people Theresa (who turned out to be the owner of that location) had called about. And we held her, and, yeah, that was that.

She showed up at that moment; we promised to send her the proof; she delivered Pearl a couple of hours later. And she hung out (I still wish I had invited her to have tea, coffee, a glass of wine, or something—she’s awesome). But I kept wondering, Pearl is adorable—why did she decide so quickly that we should have this dog?

She told us that Pearl came from Lockhart (Austin is so good about no-kill that various rescue groups draw from other cities), and that ranchers in that area really like the Anatolian Shepherd/Great Pyrenees mix because they’re great guard dogs for cattle or goats. And, she said, that’s what Pearl is. She knew this because, first, she’s seen a lot of dogs like this (they don’t spay or neuter their dogs in that area), and, second, Pearl was found in the area that has a lot of Anatolian Pyrenees.

But, still, why was she so certain we were the right owners for this puppy? When we saw Pearl, there was another person who wanted her. She’s adorable. Anyone walking into that store would want her. Why us?

So, today, I looked up Anatolian Pyrenees, and I think I figured out why she immediately decided we were the owners for this dog. Information about that mix says:

“[T]hey are not suitable dogs for inexperienced dog owners. You need to have a lot of patience to effectively train an Anatolian Pyrenees… Dog owners who don’t have a lot of experience controlling this dog’s powerful instincts should just go for another breed. Anatolian Pyrenees dogs are not casual pets. They are dominant, self-reliant dogs who will try to manage everyone and everything unless you are an assertive leader who knows how to instill respect… The Anatolian Pyrenees is a hybrid of two very energetic dogs. If you keep the Anatolian Pyrenees in a fenced-in yard at any time, be sure that the fence is at least six feet high… Owners of Anatolian Pyrenees must socialize the dogs to turn them into well-behaved companions. Even though they are intelligent and independent, they can still choose not to obey.”

We told her we have a rescue mastiff. We said one of us works from home.

Well, this will be an interesting journey.

Niemoller and the “atheists are bad because Nazis were atheist” argument

A lot of people love to quote Martin Niemoller, thinking he was a poet who wrote a poem that functions as a metaphor for complying with evil.

First they came for the Socialists, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Socialist.

Then they came for the Trade Unionists, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Trade Unionist.

Then they came for the Jews, and I did not speak out—
Because I was not a Jew.

Then they came for me—and there was no one left to speak for me.

There are various versions of it, some of which begin with the Nazis coming for communists first, and some with the Nazis coming for the Jews first. But, it wasn’t actually a poem. It was something that Neimoller said in lectures, because it wasn’t metaphorical—it was his narrative of what actually happened to him, and how he actually responded. And his whole point was that he was okay with what the Nazis did as long as he thought their policies didn’t hurt him. It was only when he ended up in jail that the problem with Nazis wasn’t their outcomes (which he liked till they hurt him), but their way. Their process was one to which he should always have objected, but he didn’t because he liked the outcome. Till he didn’t, and then he realized the process had been wrong all along.

Those processes were ones that could be used to hurt him, and so he should have paid attention to them.

I think that’s where we are. I think a lot of people are okay with Trump’s processes because they like the outcomes and they don’t realize those processes could hurt them. Niemoller realized, once he was in jail, that the ends don’t justify the means—because the means remain.

Here’s what Hitler promised: I will protect the in-group. I will institute a government that is not about fairness across groups; my policies will be entirely about promoting and protecting the in-group. That is a way  of determining policy: the government should protect and support people like me, and it’s not my business if official policy is something I would be outraged if applied to me.

Hitler said (and had always said), there are true Germans, and the German government should protect and promote their interests. That’s an argument (I will protect true Germans), and a way of arguing (laws should be applied differently depending on identity).

That second level is the one Neimoller bungled: he was fine with how the Nazis treated people until and unless it hit people like him (the Christian churches in Germany never objected to the treatment of Jews—they only mildly objected to the treatment of converted Jews; in other words, they only protected am in-group). Niemoller accepted the premised that, as long as your in-group is okay, the government is okay. Let’s think of that as the “argument from in-group/out-group” level. People might support Nazism because it seemed to support their in-group, and the hostile actions were against an out-group.[1] The way that Nazis operated—laws should be applied differently for in- versus out-group—was bad, but Niemoller was okay with it till he was a victim of that way.

This is what is important about Niemoller: his way of thinking was wrong. He was wrong because he was fine with a set of policies that applied to people that he didn’t want applied to him.

In other words, Niemoller was fine with other groups being treated in a way he would not want to be treated. It isn’t about what you’re doing; it’s about how you’re doing something. Are you treating others as you would think fair were you treated that way?

There’s a guy. He said in-group/out-group membership didn’t count. He said fairness across groups matters. Niemoller’s mistake was ignoring what that guy said, and that’s the point of his quote. People shouldn’t judge the actions of another (or a government) on the basis of whether we are harmed or benefitted at this moment, but whether we would think those actions just if applied across groups.

Hitler said (and all demagogues say), “I am you. You and I need to expel/exterminate this group that wants to exterminate us. Because they want to exterminate us, anything we do is justified.”

What Hitler did (and, to be blunt, all authoritarian demagogues do) is equivocate on the construction of that in-group. In-groups are often defined in the negative—we are this because we are not that. We take pride in not being that (to give a personal example, ELCA taking pride in not being Missouri Synod). In a culture of demagoguery, there is an out-group (Jews, communists) and any violence against that out-group is justified because they are toxic to the body politic. You demonstrate your commitment to the in-group by how much hate you express about the out-group.

When Hitler was coming to power, Niemoller was a conservative Lutheran pastor who thought the Nazis might be useful allies in regaining some of the ground lost under the socialist democrats, both in terms of the power of the church (especially Protestant) in material and cultural ways. He thought he was in Hitler’s in-group. And he thought that because there was so much rhetoric that said that there were only two sides: you could be an atheistic communist, or you could be Nazi. Hitler never argued against the many parties in the middle (including Democratic Socialists, who were not atheist, nor fascist, nor communist).

The socialists had been in favor of a separation of church and state, and so allowed secular public education, and Niemoller (and other religious figures) were worried about possibly additionally losing the substantial amount of money they got from the state. He believed, correctly, that the Nazis would not allow for the separation of church and state (whoops on how he read that belief), that they would insist on religion in the classroom, that they would have a government with an openly religious mission, and he thought he could work with them on the money issue. As far as cultural issues, Niemoller’s politics were far closer to the Nazis’ than to the socialists. He believed, correctly, that the Nazis would reinstate conservative policies regarding homosexuality, abortion, birth control, women’s rights, and religious intolerance. Niemoller was pretty typical in that regard. What that means, and this is important, is that Niemoller and people like him, because they weren’t willing to deal with a mild cutting back on their privileges, actively supported a regime that would eventually exterminate them.

And they did it because they were so obsessed with getting certain policy points–abolition of homosexuality, abortion, and birth control; a judicial system that (they thought) would promote their political agenda; financial benefits for the churches; protection of rabidly religious education—that they were willing to overlook how those policy goals would be attained.

But it’s the how that matters. Not just how policy was attained, but how people reasoned.

There is a talking point now that Nazis were atheists, and therefore atheists are bad, so, as long as we keep atheists out of office, we could never have a Holocaust. Hitler talked a lot about God, almost certainly sincerely, and, while he had some higher-level supporters who espoused atheism, most of the higher-ups were some kind of theist (even if neo-pagan), and, overwhelmingly, supporters of the regime were avowed Christian. Nazism was openly genocidal from 1939, and the genocides were not some kind of secret activity on the part of a few people. Genocide was the official and open policy of the Wehrmacht—the orders were to kill everyone who might be a political or ideological threat, and that “threat” was determined racially. People who identified as Christian stood by the side of a ditch and laughed as blood spurted from the layers of people they were killing. Had all the Christians refused to engage in genocide, the war would have ended in 1939. They didn’t. The Nazi regime was a Christian regime because most of the people enacting Nazi policies were Christian.

People who want to argue that being Christian makes someone a better person (really bad theology) and that, therefore, we should only have Christian judges and politicians, try to use Nazi Germany as an example as to why leaders should be Christian. The Nazi regime was atheist, they say, and it was bad, therefore regimes should be Christian. Not everyone in the Nazi regime was atheist, however, and most of the people who voted for, supported, and enacted Nazi policies were Christian. But, that argument is that Hitler’s entourage had a disproportionate number of atheists, and therefore atheists are dangerous. Or, Hitler’s entourage had a disproportionate number of non-Christians, and therefore this is proof that a predominantly Christian government is safe.

Here’s the problem with how people tend to argue (and it’s the problem Niemoller was trying to point to): it isn’t what you argue; it’s how you argue. For a long time, all he cared about was what people were arguing, and then he suddenly realized that what mattered was how they argued.

Milton Mayer’s troubling book They Thought They Were Free describes ten people who submitted to Nazism cheerfully, and who continued to believe that Hitler was good (but had bad advisors). It has a brilliant explanation as to why they continued to believe in Hitler, and one part of the explanation is that people tend to think in the short term as to whether they are, in this moment, better, and not whether the way they got the things they like is a good way. Mayer says that they believed “Adolf Hitler was good—in my friends’ view—up until 1943, 1941, or 1939, depending on the individual’s assessment of his strategy” (69-70). In other words, he was good for Germany until things started to go bad, but Hitler’s strategy was bad from the beginning—his was of deliberating, his plans for world domination, his racist policies. It’s as though they thought that drinking arsenic was great till the moment it killed someone—they didn’t acknowledge that the way Hitler ruled was always going to end up in an unwinnable war, racial extermination, and a devastated Germany.

There are a lot of ways to assess an argument; here I want to mention three. First, it’s a good argument because it’s made by someone you thinking is good. Second, it’s a good argument because it confirms your beliefs, and so it intuitively feels right. Third, it’s a good argument because the way it’s argued would be, you think, a good way to argue even if you didn’t like the outcome.[2] There is a similar division in terms of thinking about politics: you can decide that a policy is good because it’s advocated by someone you like; or it’s good because you’re benefitting from it here and now; or it’s good because the way it was argued and enacted and applied would be, you think, good even if you didn’t benefit from it.

The argument that Nazism was atheist fits into the first and second categories, but not the third. It is probably made by people you like, and it gets you a conclusion you like (Christians are good and Nazis are bad). But the way it’s argued—if you consistently applied that logic—would lead to your endorsing Nazi policies.

I say, “Kale is bad because I threw up after eating it.” If I sincerely believed that was a good way to argue, then I’d be willing to stop consuming anything that made me throw up. [In rhetorical terms, the enthymeme has a major premise I’ll support in other circumstances.] But, what if I threw up after drinking tequila? If I’m going to stick with the premise established in regard to kale, then I’d also conclude that tequila is bad (personally, I’d support that conclusion), in which case my argument about kale is logical. But, what if I ever want to drink tequila again (and, really, I’d say you should think about that), then my conclusion about tequila has a different premise from my argument about tequila.

In other words, the major premise of my stance about kale (things that make me throw up should be avoided) is not one I hold consistently, so it isn’t actually helping me make decisions about what to consume. It’s only helping me rationalize decisions I make for other reasons.

If I like tequila (really, why would you do that?), I’ll find lots of reasons to exempt it from the “it makes you throw up” argument I’m willing to make for kale. And that’s the important point, if I’m not willing to reason across kale and tequila, then I don’t have a logical argument. I’m just looking for reasons to hate kale and like tequila (don’t—don’t do that).

If my way of making decisions is to protect my commitments, then I will start with a premise (kale is bad), and I will just look for datapoints to support that premise. And here’s what’s important for thinking about how people reason—I will feel that I am logical in my feelings about kale since I can find lots of evidence to support my claim. You can find lots of evidence to support any claim, after all. What you can’t find (and this is where Infowars and conspiracy theories get it wrong), is evidence that you apply with consistent premises. But that’s a different pot. Here’s the point I’m making: if I’m not actually willing to apply my reasoning about kale to other things that make me throw up, then I’m not being logical; I’m just neck-deep in the swamp of confirmation bias.

It might be true that kale is bad, but kale being bad doesn’t confirm my way of reasoning. What I mean by that is that it might be true that Nazis are bad political leaders (they are), but that doesn’t mean that Christians are good political leaders. Nazis weren’t bad because some of the Nazi leaders were atheists; Nazis were bad because they were entitled authoritarian racist fascist militarist German exceptionalists who rejected any notions of universal human rights. The Nazi way of reasoning never changed, but its outcomes did—what Mayer shows is that, when that way got people what they wanted, it seemed good; when it didn’t it got bad. They didn’t see that the bad was the inevitable consequence of the apparently good.  The Nazi way of reasoning initially seemed good to Niemoller, because it got him what he wanted. But it wasn’t a good way, because it got him in jail. And then he saw it was bad—it was bad all along, but he didn’t see it till he was in jail.[3]

What the Nazis should teach us is that our group succeeding is not a good reason to support a politician—we should support politicians who advocate policies we would support regardless of whether they benefit us personally. And we shouldn’t just judge an argument as to whether it gets a conclusion we like; we should think about whether we would consider it a good way of arguing for everyone.

And that’s where the “Atheists are bad because the Nazis were bad” gets awful. That argument assumes that you can and should take disproportionate representation of some group in a bad power structure as proof that the group as a whole is evil. Nazis were evil, you reason, and a disproportionate were atheist, and so all atheists are dangerous. So, if that’s a good way to argue, then if a disproportionate number of leaders of Pol Pot’s revolution were left-handed, we should consider left-handed people evil. Or, if a disproportionate number of people in Lenin’s group were Jews, then Jews are bad.

And that is exactly how Nazis did (and do) argue. So, if you think that the presence of atheists in the Nazi regime is proof that Nazism is essentially atheist (regardless of the religious affiliations of the people who enacted Nazi policies) then you’re a Nazi. Lenin’s group had a disproportionate number of Jews, so, your logic says the Nazis were logical to say all Jews are essentially bad. That’s how you reason.

I’m not saying that you think Jews are essentially bad. I’m saying you’re Niemoller. Niemoller didn’t think Protestants should be jailed. But he didn’t like communists or socialists or Jews. And he knew that the Nazis would violate laws and act in authoritarian ways to exterminate out-groups. For a long time, he was only concerned with the outcome of their policies, and not the way they enacted their policies. Hitler was a liar, and had always been a liar, but, when Hitler told a lie Niemoller liked, Hitler’s way of arguing or administering didn’t matter. It was only when Niemoller ended up in jail that he realized Hitler’s way was wrong, and it had always been wrong.

The way matters. If you think that atheists can’t be trusted because leading Nazis were disproportionately atheist, then you think the Nazis were right about the Jews. Or, in other words, you aren’t really thinking.

[1] And here I have to stop and explain that sociologists use the in-group/out-group distinction in a very specific and useful way. People often use “in-group” to mean people in power, but sociologists use it to mean the group you’re in. So, while pitbull owners is not a politically central group, it’s an in-group for people who believe that owning a pitbull is an important part of their identity.

[2] I am in an intermittent state of rage as to how scholars in rhetoric talk about Aristotle’s ethos/pathos/logos—it’s read in light of logical positivists logic/emotion binary. If you read what Aristotle says about politics and ethics, however, I think you end up with something much more like what I’m saying here.

[3] I’d also say it matters because all scams—ethical or monetary—rely on getting people to ignore major premises. If you want to scam someone, you get them to reason the wrong premises. Someone sells you a bad car on the grounds that he’s a nice guy; someone gets you to vote for her on the grounds that she is like you; someone persuades you to buy property on the grounds that he’s sold other property that made money. Those are all arguments that rely on major premises that are obviously invalid.